Logo for M Libraries Publishing

Want to create or adapt books like this? Learn more about how Pressbooks supports open publishing practices.

4.3 Causation and Harm

Learning objectives.

  • Distinguish between factual and legal cause.
  • Define intervening superseding cause, and explain the role it plays in the defendant’s criminal liability.
  • Define one and three years and a day rules.

As stated previously, causation and harm can also be elements of a criminal offense if the offense requires a bad result. In essence, if injury is required under the statute, or the case is in a jurisdiction that allows for common-law crimes, the defendant must cause the requisite harm . Many incidents occur when the defendant technically initiates circumstances that result in harm, but it would be unjust to hold the defendant criminally responsible. Thus causation should not be rigidly determined in every instance, and the trier of fact must perform an analysis that promotes fairness. In this section, causation in fact and legal causation are examined as well as situations where the defendant may be insulated from criminal responsibility.

Figure 4.9 Oregon Revised Statutes

Oregon Revised Statutes

Causation in Fact

Every causation analysis is twofold. First, the defendant must be the factual or but for cause of the victim’s harm. The but for term comes from this phrase: “but for the defendant’s act, the harm would not have occurred” (Del. Code Ann. tit. II, 2011). As the Model Penal Code states, “[c]onduct is the cause of a result when…(a) it is an antecedent but for which the result in question would not have occurred” (Model Penal Code § 2.03(1)(a)). Basically, the defendant is the factual or but for cause of the victim’s harm if the defendant’s act starts the chain of events that leads to the eventual result.

Example of Factual Cause

Henry and Mary get into an argument over their child custody agreement. Henry gives Mary a hard shove. Mary staggers backward, is struck by lightning, and dies instantly. In this example, Henry’s act forced Mary to move into the area where the lighting happened to strike. However, it would be unjust to punish Henry for Mary’s death in this case because Henry could not have imagined the eventual result. Thus although Henry is the factual or but for cause of Mary’s death, he is probably not the legal cause .

Legal Causation

It is the second part of the analysis that ensures fairness in the application of the causation element. The defendant must also be the legal or proximate cause of the harm. Proximate means “near,” so the defendant’s conduct must be closely related to the harm it engenders. As the Model Penal Code states, the actual result cannot be “too remote or accidental in its occurrence to have a [just] bearing on the actor’s liability” (Model Penal Code § 2.03 (2) (b)).

The test for legal causation is objective foreseeability (California Criminal Jury Instructions No. 520, 2011). The trier of fact must be convinced that when the defendant acted, a reasonable person could have foreseen or predicted that the end result would occur. In the example given in Section 4 “Example of Factual Cause” , Henry is not the legal cause of Mary’s death because a reasonable person could have neither foreseen nor predicted that a shove would push Mary into a spot where lightning was about to strike.

The Model Penal Code adjusts the legal causation foreseeability requirement depending on whether the defendant acted purposely, knowingly, recklessly, or negligently. If the defendant’s behavior is reckless or negligent, the legal causation foreseeability requirement is analyzed based on the risk of harm, rather than the purpose of the defendant.

Example of Legal Causation

Imagine that Henry and Mary get into the same argument over their child custody agreement, but this time they are in their garage, which is crowded with furniture. Henry gives Mary a hard shove, even though she is standing directly in front of a large entertainment center filled with books and a heavy thirty-two-inch television set. Mary staggers backward into the entertainment center and it crashes down on top of her, killing her. In this situation, Henry is the factual cause of Mary’s death because he started the chain of events that led to her death with his push. In addition, it is foreseeable that Mary might suffer a serious injury or death when shoved directly into a large and heavy piece of furniture. Thus in this example, Henry could be the factual and legal cause of Mary’s death. It is up to the trier of fact to make this determination based on an assessment of objective foreseeability and the attendant circumstances.

Intervening Superseding Cause

Another situation where the defendant is the factual but not the legal cause of the requisite harm is when something or someone interrupts the chain of events started by the defendant. This is called an intervening superseding cause . Typically, an intervening superseding cause cuts the defendant off from criminal liability because it is much closer, or proximate , to the resulting harm (Connecticut Jury Instructions No. 2.6-1, 2011). If an intervening superseding cause is a different individual acting with criminal intent, the intervening individual is criminally responsible for the harm caused.

Example of an Intervening Superseding Cause

Review the example with Henry and Mary in Section 4 “Example of Legal Causation” . Change the example so that Henry pulls out a knife and chases Mary out of the garage. Mary escapes Henry and hides in an abandoned shed. Half an hour later, Wes, a homeless man living in the shed, returns from a day of panhandling. When he discovers Mary in the shed, he kills her and steals her money and jewelry. In this case, Henry is still the factual cause of Mary’s death, because he chased her into the shed where she was eventually killed. However, Wes is probably the intervening superseding cause of Mary’s death because he interrupted the chain of events started by Henry. Thus Wes is subject to prosecution for Mary’s death, and Henry may be prosecuted only for assault with a deadly weapon.

One and Three Years and a Day Rules

In criminal homicide cases, the causation analysis could be complicated by a victim’s survival for an extended time period. Because of modern technology, victims often stay alive on machines for many years after they have been harmed. However, it may be unreasonable to hold a defendant responsible for a death that occurs several years after the defendant’s criminal act. A few states have rules that solve this dilemma.

Some states have either a one year and a day rule or a three years and a day rule (S.C. Code Ann., 2011). These rules create a timeline for the victim’s death that changes the causation analysis in a criminal homicide case. Under one or three years and a day rules, the victim of a criminal homicide must die within the specified time limits for the defendant to be criminally responsible. If the victim does not die within the time limits, the defendant may be charged with attempted murder , rather than criminal homicide. California makes the timeline a rebuttable presumption that can be overcome with evidence proving that the conduct was criminal and the defendant should still be convicted (Cal. Penal Code, 2011).

Figure 4.10 California Penal Code

California Penal Code

Death timeline rules are often embodied in a state’s common law and have lost popularity in recent years (Key v. State, 2011). Thus many states have abolished arbitrary time limits for the victim’s death in favor of ordinary principles of legal causation (Rogers v. Tennessee, 2011). Death timeline rules are not to be confused with the statute of limitations , which is the time limit the government has to prosecute a criminal defendant.

Figure 4.11 Diagram of the Elements of a Crime

Diagram of the Elements of a Crime

Key Takeaways

  • Factual cause means that the defendant starts the chain of events leading to the harm. Legal cause means that the defendant is held criminally responsible for the harm because the harm is a foreseeable result of the defendant’s criminal act.
  • An intervening superseding cause breaks the chain of events started by the defendant’s act and cuts the defendant off from criminal responsibility.
  • One and three years and a day rules create a timeline for the victim’s death in a criminal homicide.

Answer the following questions. Check your answers using the answer key at the end of the chapter.

  • Phillipa sees Fred picking up trash along the highway and decides she wants to frighten him. She drives a quarter of a mile ahead of Fred and parks her car. She then hides in the bushes and waits for Fred to show up. When Fred gets close enough, she jumps out of the bushes screaming. Frightened, Fred drops his trash bag and runs into the middle of the highway where he is struck by a vehicle and killed. Is Phillipa’s act the legal cause of Fred’s death? Why or why not?
  • Read Bullock v. State , 775 A.2d. 1043 (2001). In Bullock , the defendant was convicted of manslaughter based on a vehicle collision that occurred when his vehicle hit the victim’s vehicle in an intersection. The defendant was under the influence of alcohol and traveling thirty miles per hour over the speed limit. The victim was in the intersection unlawfully because the light was red. The defendant claimed that the victim was the intervening superseding cause of her own death. Did the Supreme Court of Delaware agree? The case is available at this link: http://caselaw.findlaw.com/de-supreme-court/1137701.html .
  • Read Commonwealth v. Casanova , 429 Mass. 293 (1999). In Casanova , the defendant shot the victim in 1991, paralyzing him. The defendant was convicted of assault with intent to murder and two firearms offenses. In 1996, the victim died. The defendant was thereafter indicted for his murder. Massachusetts had abolished the year and a day rule in 1980. Did the Massachusetts Supreme Judicial Court uphold the indictment, or did the court establish a new death timeline rule? The case is available at this link: http://scholar.google.com/scholar_case?case=16055857562232849296&hl=en&as_sdt=2&as_vis=1&oi=scholarr .

Cal. Penal Code § 194, accessed February 14, 2011, http://codes.lp.findlaw.com/cacode/PEN/3/1/8/1/s194 .

California Criminal Jury Instructions No. 520, accessed February 14, 2011, http://www.justia.com/criminal/docs/calcrim/500/520.html .

Connecticut Jury Instructions No. 2.6-1, accessed February 14, 2011, http://www.jud.ct.gov/ji/criminal/part2/2.6-1.htm .

Del. Code Ann. tit. II, § 261, accessed February 14, 2011, http://delcode.delaware.gov/title11/c002/index.shtml#261 .

Key v. State , 890 So.2d 1043 (2002), accessed February 15, 2011, http://www.lexisone.com/lx1/caselaw/freecaselaw?action= OCLGetCaseDetail&format=FULL&sourceID=beehed&searchTerm= efiQ.QLea.aadj.eaOS&searchFlag=y&l1loc=FCLOW .

Rogers v. Tennessee , 532 U.S. 541 (2001), accessed February 14, 2011, http://caselaw.lp.findlaw.com/scripts/getcase.pl?court=us&vol=000&invol=99-6218 .

S.C. Code Ann. § 56-5-2910, accessed February 15, 2011, http://www.scstatehouse.gov/code/t56c005.htm .

Criminal Law Copyright © 2015 by University of Minnesota is licensed under a Creative Commons Attribution-NonCommercial-ShareAlike 4.0 International License , except where otherwise noted.

McGill Law Journal

Causation, Fault, and Fairness in the Criminal Law

Over the past two decades, the Supreme Court of Canada has developed an overarching account of causation rooted in the need to prevent the conviction of the morally innocent. Despite these valuable contributions, there are certain limitations to the way causation is currently conceptualized in Canadian criminal law. This article aims to address those limitations and offer a plausible alternative account of causation and its underlying rationale. It advances three core arguments. First, it explains why judges should employ one uniform formulation of the factual causation standard: significant contributing cause. Second, it offers a new account of legal causation that distinguishes foreseeability as part of the actus reus from foreseeability inherent to mens rea. In doing so, it sets out why legal causation is primarily concerned with fairly ascribing ambits of risk to individuals. Third, it refutes the Supreme Court of Canada’s underlying justification for the causation requirement. Contrary to the Court’s invocation of the importance of moral innocence, this article demonstrates that causation principles actually tend to concede the accused’s moral fault while still providing reasons for withholding blame for a given consequence. This reveals that causation’s underlying rationale is more closely related to concerns about fair attribution rather than moral innocence. Ultimately, this article reframes causation to better answer one of the most basic questions in the criminal law: Why am I being blamed for this?

Au cours des deux dernières décennies, la Cour suprême du Canada a élaboré une explication générale de la causalité ancrée dans la nécessité d’éviter la condamnation de personnes moralement innocentes. Malgré ces contributions importantes, il existe certaines limites à la façon dont la causalité est présentement conceptualisée en droit criminel canadien. Cet article aborde ces limites et propose une alternative plausible pour expliquer la causalité et sa justification sous-jacente. Il met de l’avant trois arguments principaux. Premièrement, il explique pourquoi les juges devraient employer une formulation uniforme de la norme de causalité factuelle : la cause à la contribution significative. Deuxièmement, il propose une nouvelle définition de la causalité juridique qui distingue la prévisibilité faisant partie de l’actus reus de la prévisibilité inhérente à la mens rea. Ce faisant, il expose les raisons pour lesquelles la causalité juridique a pour objet principal d’attribuer équitablement les étendues des risques aux individus. Troisièmement, il réfute la justification sous-jacente à l’exigence de causalité donnée par la Cour suprême du Canada. Contrairement à la Cour, qui invoque l’importance de l’innocence morale, cet article démontre que les principes de causalité tendent en fait à admettre la faute morale de l’accusé tout en fournissant des motifs pour ne pas porter de blâme relativement à une conséquence donnée. Cela révèle que le raisonnement sous-jacent à la causalité est plus étroitement lié aux préoccupations concernant l’aspect équitable de l’attribution du blâme qu’à l’innocence morale de l’accusé. En fin de compte, cet article reformule la causalité pour mieux répondre à l’une des questions les plus fondamentales du droit criminel : pourquoi suis-je tenu responsable de cela?

* Assistant professor, University of Ottawa, Faculty of Law, Civil Law Section. I thank Professors Don Stuart and Graham Mayeda for their comments on prior drafts. I also thank Anna Maria Konewka, Edward Béchard-Torres, Olga Redko, Will Colish, Jessy Héroux, Michelle Biddulph, Hadi Ghobril, Bilal Amani, Nadreyh Vagba, Rayene Bouzitoun, and the anonymous reviewers for helping refine my arguments and commenting on earlier versions of this article. All mistakes are my own. Lastly, I thank the MLJ editorial team for their excellent work that improved this article significantly.

Table of Contents

Introduction.

Suppose that the accused points a gun at the victim and shoots several times. The victim dies immediately. In such contexts, the causal chain between the accused’s conduct and the victim’s death is clear. The accused’s actions contributed to the victim’s death in a physical, medical, or mechanistic sense—the threshold question of factual causation (or cause in fact). [1] That, however, is not the end of the causation inquiry in Canadian criminal law. There must also be legal causation (or cause in law), meaning that it is fair to ascribe the victim’s death to the accused’s conduct—or, in other words, that the accused is morally responsible for the victim’s death. [2]

In other cases, causation is less evident. A third party may attack the victim between the time of the accused’s initial assault and the victim’s death. [3] Some natural cause or event may also play a role in the victim’s death. [4] Third parties may apply some form of negligent care that also contributes to the victim’s death. [5] The victim may die after refusing life-saving care for injuries inflicted by the accused. [6] In all of these cases, some type of intervening event, cause, or act (a novus actus interveniens ) obscures causation. [7]

The causation inquiry is fundamental in the criminal law for a variety of reasons. Intervening acts raise concerns that touch on issues of fair labelling, culpability, and punishment. [8] These concerns are at the forefront when an accused risks being stigmatized for causing an injury or death for which they are not uniquely responsible. [9] Despite the persistence and importance of these issues, courts and scholars correctly point out that causation is notoriously complex and difficult to articulate. [10] It involves the interplay between metaphysical, scientific, moral, and legal considerations. [11]

This article aims to advance a more cogent and clear conception of the causation requirement in Canadian criminal law. Its principal arguments and structure are as follows.

Part I describes the distinction between factual and legal causation as articulated by the Supreme Court of Canada. Building on Jeremy Butt’s recent scholarship, Part II argues that judges should use a uniform formulation of the factual causation standard: significant contributing cause. [12] It also shows why the but-for test is unhelpful except in the easiest of cases. [13] Part II provides the groundwork for this article’s core argument about the role of factual causation—ascribing negative changes in the world to individuals. This Part demonstrates why the significant contributing cause test helps ensure a strong ascriptive link between the defendant’s conduct and its role in worsening others’ plights.

Part III then sets out a plausible account of legal causation’s function as part of a broader causation analysis. It first shows how Canadian criminal law tends to assess an intervening act’s reasonable foreseeability rather than its independence, and how the latter test is subsumed by the former. It then argues that the doctrine of reasonable foreseeability is distinct from the question of foreseeability of bodily harm when assessing moral fault. The doctrine remains useful as an analytical tool to evaluate legal causation, serving to limit criminal liability where unforeseeable contributing causes fall outside the ambit of risk associated with the accused’s initial conduct.

Part IV then challenges the Supreme Court of Canada’s account of the role of factual and legal causation in the criminal law (namely, that they aim to prevent the conviction of morally innocent persons). [14] This Part shows why legal causation can concede the moral culpability of individuals who significantly contribute to the victim’s death, yet withhold blame due to concerns that are rooted in principles of ascription and fair labelling—rationales that are distinct from moral innocence. [15] Ultimately, this article explains why, like other legal doctrines, causation touches on one of the most crucial issues in the criminal law: Who is responsible for what ?

I.  Factual and Legal Causation Generally

Causation is a necessary component of the actus reus for result crimes, [16] meaning crimes that are “in part defined by certain consequences which follow an act.” [17] Those results or consequences include death (e.g., for the crimes of manslaughter, criminal negligence causing death, or murder) or bodily harm (e.g., for the offences of assault causing bodily harm or criminal negligence causing bodily harm). [18] The causation component of the actus reus for result crimes is divided into a two-step inquiry. First, there must be factual causation between the accused’s conduct and the consequence. [19] If the first step is satisfied, the second step examines legal causation—whether the accused is morally responsible for the victim’s death. [20]

A.  Factual Causation

The Supreme Court of Canada explains that factual causation (or cause in fact) implies the accused’s “medical, mechanical, or physical” contribution to the victim’s injury or death . [21] Cause in fact is a necessary precondition that ties the accused’s conduct to the consequence. [22] While medical expert reports and testimony can assist in establishing factual causation, [23] the trier of fact ultimately determines whether cause in fact is established and is not restricted to a medical expert’s conclusion on that point. [24] In clear cases, the cause in fact inquiry is often framed in counterfactual terms: the victim would not have died or suffered gross bodily harm but for the accused’s contribution to that result. [25]

The Supreme Court of Canada initially explored the requisite degree of factual causation in Smithers . [26] Writing on behalf of the unanimous Court, Justice Dickson (as he then was) concluded that the accused’s conduct must contribute to the victim’s injury or death “outside the de minimis range.” [27] Consistent with the causation test in other countries, it is not necessary that the accused’s act be the sole cause of the victim’s injury or death. [28] The Court also affirmed the longstanding “thin skull principle” applicable in civil and criminal law. [29] According to that principle, causation subsists where the victim had a pre-existing medical condition (e.g., hemophilia, a thin skull, or low bone density) that increased the likelihood of death. [30] The accused thus takes the victim as they find them. [31]

The causation threshold established in Smithers was revisited in R. v. Nette . The Court affirmed that in assessing causation in the criminal law, the concept of contributory negligence does not apply. [32] The majority of the Court also reformulated the terminology for factual causation, holding that the accused’s conduct must be a “significant contributing cause” of the victim’s injury or death. [33] In the Court’s view, it was simpler for triers of fact to understand causation described in positive terms (e.g., a significant contribution) as opposed to in negative terms (e.g., a not insignificant contribution). [34] The majority held that trial judges nonetheless can instruct juries using either formulation—an approach that is criticized below in Part II. [35]

B.  Legal Causation

Legal causation (or cause in law) concerns the legitimacy of holding an accused morally responsible for a given result. [36] In contexts where the defendant contributes significantly to the victim’s death and there is no intervening act or event, legal causation is relatively simple. Cause in law is more difficult to ascertain when another event or act also contributes to the victim’s death. Such cases raise concerns about whether it is fair to blame the accused for that result. [37] The second prong of the causation analysis therefore helps ensure that the victim’s injury or death is morally attributable to the actor’s role in producing those consequences. [38]

Both the Criminal Code and the common law provide rules governing legal causation. [39] Certain Criminal Code provisions maintain cause in law despite the acts of a third party or the victim that play some role in the latter’s death. Section 224 establishes that if the defendant injures the victim, causation subsists despite the victim’s failure to resort to proper means that would have prevented their death. [40] Notably, legal causation remains intact where the victim refuses life-saving treatment, for either religious or other reasons. [41] Section 225 affirms legal causation where the victim dies as a result of good faith but inappropriately applied medical care. [42]

The common law rules from the Maybin decision set out two analytical tools that assist courts in determining whether an intervening act undermines cause in law. [43] The first analytical tool assesses whether the general nature of the intervening act and its accompanying risk of harm were reasonably foreseeable at the time of the accused’s initial conduct (“reasonably foreseeable intervening acts”). [44] Where that threshold is met, legal causation is generally maintained. [45] The intervening act’s reasonable foreseeability famously justified maintaining causation in the Supreme Court of South Australia’s decision Hallett . [46] In that case, the accused attacked the victim and left him unconscious on a beach. The tide rose and the victim drowned. The Court held that the rising tide was reasonably foreseeable, and the accused was convicted of manslaughter. [47]

The same test justified maintaining legal causation in the Ontario Court of Appeal decision R. v. Shilon . [48] In that case, an individual stole a motorcycle. A high-speed car chase ensued, involving the stolen motorcycle’s owner (Trakas) and the accused (Shilon), who participated in the motorcycle theft but escaped in another vehicle. While chasing Shilon, Trakas’s car struck and killed a police officer who was laying down a stop-stick. Both Trakas and Shilon were accused of criminal negligence causing death. At issue was whether Trakas’s conduct was an intervening act that undermined Shilon’s responsibility for causing the officer’s demise. [49] The Court upheld Shilon’s conviction, concluding that Trakas’s actions and the risk of harm were reasonably foreseeable consequences of Shilon’s conduct. [50]

The second analytical tool assesses whether the intervening act was independent of the accused’s conduct and deemed to be the sole legal cause of the victim’s death (“independent intervening acts”). [51] Such acts are generally associated with voluntary conduct of a third party or of the victim that also played some role in the latter’s injury or death. [52] Independent acts are said to create new causal chains and sever the accused’s legal responsibility for a given result. [53]

Independent intervening acts imply that the accused’s conduct only set the scene for some other act to cause the victim’s death and therefore was not instrumental in causing it. [54] Where the accused’s actions are merely part of the background, history, or context for the intervening act, the accused is absolved of blame for having caused the relevant result. [55] Where the intervening act is a direct or immediate response to the accused’s actions, the accused is still held responsible in law for that result. [56]

II. Toward a Uniform Formulation for Factual Causation

A.  “beyond de minimis” versus “significant contributing cause”.

The Supreme Court of Canada accepts that judges possess discretion with respect to the formulation of the factual causation standard. [57] This Part discusses the problems associated with varying terminology of that standard. It argues that the beyond de minimis test, but-for test, and significant contributing cause test are different and should not be used interchangeably. It then provides reasons why only the “significant contributing cause” formulation should be used in Canadian criminal law.

In the Supreme Court of Canada decision R. v. Nette , Justice Arbour wrote that trial judges are afforded significant latitude in describing the factual causation test. She explained:

As I discussed in  Cribbin , while different terminology has been used to explain the applicable standard in Canada, Australia and England, whether the terminology used is “beyond  de minimis ”, “significant contribution” or “substantial cause”, the standard of causation which this terminology seeks to articulate, within the context of causation in homicide, is essentially the same. [58]

Some scholars disagree that both formulations for cause in fact—beyond de minimis and significant contributing cause—are interchangeable. Stanley Yeo posits that a not insignificant contribution does not equate to a significant contribution. [59] He remarks: “[W]hen Mary says that she does not dislike John, she means, at most, that she is impartial towards him rather than that she likes him.” [60] Four out of the nine Supreme Court Justices in Nette shared a similar view. They explained: “To claim that something not unimportant is important would be a sophism. Likewise, to consider things that are not dissimilar to be similar would amount to an erroneous interpretation.” [61] Hugues Parent also rejects the equivalency between both standards. In his view, the significant contributing cause standard in Nette is more demanding than the beyond the de minimis range standard in Smithers . [62]

In light of the plausible difference between both formulations for cause in fact, scholars argue against allowing judges to employ different terminology interchangeably. Many criticize the continued use of the beyond the de minimis threshold on the grounds that virtually any contribution by the accused will satisfy the test’s demands. [63] In support of that contention, Jill Presser notes:

[V]irtually all conditions that are precipitating factors of a consequence may be said to be causes. The de minimis threshold is set so low that there is no need to stipulate the requirement of a direct causal relationship between the unlawful act and the proscribed harm. [64]

David Tanovich and James Lockyer agree with that position. In line with certain judicial decisions, they characterize the Smithers causation standard as “sweeping.” [65]

Anne-Marie Boisvert, for her part, contends that one better understands the lax standard set out in Smithers by also considering the range of circumstances that fail to break the causal chain. [66] She points out that the beyond de minimis test not only requires little contribution from the accused to meet that threshold, but dismisses an array (or combination) of relevant contributing circumstances as irrelevant. [67] Those circumstances can include the victim’s pre-existing medical condition, their refusal to receive life-saving care, negligent medical treatment provided by others, and contributory negligence. [68]

For similar reasons, the Law Reform Commission of Canada contended that the but-for and beyond de minimis standards could produce irrational conclusions––for example, that marriage is a cause of divorce. [69] The Commission ultimately argued in favour of a causation test requiring the accused to contribute significantly to the result. [70]

Don Stuart posits that it is plausible that the adoption of the beyond de minimis standard can lead to convictions where the significant contributing cause standard can result in acquittals. [71] He offers the example of the Ontario Court of Appeal decision R. v. Shanks . [72] During a brief altercation, the defendant threw the elderly victim to the ground. The victim, who suffered from a range of pre-existing medical conditions, died later that evening from a heart attack after coronary plaque dislodged and obstructed one of his arteries. Expert evidence revealed that there was an 80–90 per cent chance that the heart attack would have occurred even without the assault. The trial judge still convicted the accused of manslaughter, concluding that he contributed to the victim’s death beyond the de minimis range. [73] The Ontario Court of Appeal upheld the conviction. Don Stuart suggests that the trier of fact may have acquitted the defendant had the significant contributing cause standard been employed. [74]

B.  Toward the Uniform Standard of Significant Contributing Cause

There are certain advantages to uniformly employing the significant contributing cause test for factual causation, rather than allowing judges to use different terminology, including “beyond de minimis .” First, the significant contributing cause threshold may promote fair labelling and proportionate stigmatization, especially in cases where the defendant’s contribution to the victim’s death is questionable. [75] For some result crimes other than murder—such as manslaughter or criminal negligence—the defendant risks being stigmatized for causing another’s death. [76] If convicted of those offences, defendants can be sentenced to life imprisonment. [77] The dangers of unfair attribution become particularly prominent in contexts where pre-existing medical conditions or vulnerabilities significantly increase the chance of victims’ suffering injury or death from relatively banal acts. The greater the victim’s vulnerability, the easier it is for the accused’s act to injure the victim or cause their death. Given those risks, the significant contribution test may better protect against unfair attribution of certain results to the accused.

Second, a more demanding causation standard is consistent with other principles that favour fair blaming and punishment practices, such as the principle of lenity (or strict construction) applicable to the statutory interpretation of criminal laws. [78] Strict construction governs the circumstances in which ambiguous criminal law statutes are interpreted in the defendant’s favour. [79] Lenity is not a freestanding principle that automatically applies to penal statutes. [80] Rather, as Glanville Williams explains, it is employed where a penal statute gives rise to more than one reasonable interpretation that is nonetheless consistent with the legislator’s objective. [81] Lenity aims to protect individuals against disproportionate attributions of blame, stigma, or punishment in light of the defendant’s actual culpability. [82] Admittedly, the causation standard is not a statutory creation or an ambiguous penal statute; it is a common law creation. Yet ambiguity about the appropriate causation standard raises the same concern that underpins the lenity principle: fair labelling. Supreme Court judges’ disagreement in Nette as to whether non-insignificance equates to significance exemplifies the type of ambiguity that militates in favour of lenity in other contexts.

Third, the importance of predictability and uniformity in the criminal law supports the adoption of one single formulation for factual causation. If nearly half the Supreme Court judges in Nette perceived a meaningful difference between different formulations of the causation test, it is conceivable that other judges or jury members do as well. [83]

Fourth, the sole use of the significant contributing cause test would standardize the factual causation threshold in cases with and without intervening acts. In Nette , the Supreme Court of Canada held that judges have discretion to determine the formulation of the causation standard. [84] Yet several years later in Maybin , the Court was more explicit about the formulation of the causation standard in the presence of intervening acts: it was significant contributing cause. [85] Canadian courts as well as the England and Wales Court of Appeal (citing Maybin and prior English cases) affirmed that approach in homicide cases, highlighting the need to ensure that the accused’s contribution to the victim’s death is significant. [86] Where causation issues arise, the core question is always the same: whether the accused contributed significantly to the victim’s death in fact and in law. [87] This remains the fundamental question irrespective of some intervening act, where courts militate strongly in favour of the sole formulation of significant contributing cause. For that reason, the causation formulation applicable in contexts of novus actus interveniens should also be used in contexts where there is no intervening act.

C.  Limitations to But-For Causation

Factual causation generally involves the counterfactual but-for inquiry: but for the accused’s act, the victim would not be injured or deceased. [88] As reiterated on numerous occasions, the accused’s contribution need not be the predominant, most significant, or most direct cause of death. [89] In many contexts, but-for causation is unhelpful and inevitably requires an assessment of significant contributing cause––a factor that further militates in favour of employing one formulation of the factual causation threshold. [90]

Ernest Weinrib explains that the but-for test is a speculative process that considers “what did not happen or rather what would have happened if what had happened had not happened.” [91] As is the case in tort law jurisprudence, certain scenarios render the but-for test futile . [92] The test is ill-suited where multiple defendants contribute to some extent to the victim’s death and it is unclear what would have transpired but for a particular defendant’s involvement. [93] Furthermore, the but-for test is unhelpful where death would have ensued even without the accused’s act, such as in cases where the accused prematurely kills a victim that is on the verge of death. [94] The test is also inadequate in the presence of intervening acts, where courts must engage in a form of contrastive causation that necessarily assesses the significance of the accused’s contribution to the victim’s death. [95]

Michael Moore argues that but-for causation can be problematic because it does not generally consider the intensity of one’s contribution to a result. [96] Consequently, in hard cases, courts must necessarily depart from but-for causation and examine whether the accused contributed significantly to the victim’s death—the precise approach adopted by the Supreme Court of Canada in Nette and Maybin . [97] In a similar vein, Butt points out that courts convict defendants where they contribute significantly to the victim’s death despite not being the but-for cause of that result. This is notably the case where multiple co-principals attack a victim, yet each attack is sufficient to cause death. [98]

Similarly, courts assess the significance of the defendant’s contribution to a result in contexts where several co-principals mutually engage in some conduct that creates serious risks of harm and results in death. For instance, in R. v. Menezes , the defendant was street racing against another vehicle, driven by Meuszynski. [99] At some point, Meuszynski’s car left the roadway and collided with a utility pole. He died in the accident. At issue was whether Menezes could be convicted of criminal negligence causing death for having co-participated in the street race. [100] Justice Hill Jr. declared that the defendant could not exculpate himself on the basis of the victim’s contributory negligence, [101] observing that factual causation could be satisfied even though the defendant did not physically collide with the deceased’s vehicle. [102] The judge applied the significant contributing cause test, interrogating whether the defendant’s contribution to the death was sufficiently material as opposed to collateral. [103] Justice Hill Jr. reasoned that co-participants in a street race both assume responsibility for the danger created by this jointly maintained activity, including for the death of one of the drivers—an approach adopted by other courts in similar cases. [104] Likewise, in contexts involving shootouts between co-principals, courts have held that one co-principal factually contributes to a victim’s death resulting from the other co-principal’s gunshot. [105] In these types of cases, courts evaluate the accused’s factual involvement in bringing about a consequence by looking at its intensity—whether the contribution is so significant that it cannot logically be divorced from the consequence.

These types of concerns lead some scholars to observe that the but-for test is most useful only in the easiest cases, where it is least needed. [106] Recognizing that harder cases inevitably require a consideration of the extent of the accused’s contribution to a result, Weinrib suggests that courts could avoid using but-for causation in many cases. [107] He remarks: “[I]t may be best to acknowledge that we can come no closer to an adequate solution of the cause in fact problem than to confront it directly by asking simply whether the defendant’s conduct was a substantial factor in producing the injury” [108] —a suggestion that acknowledges the necessity of examining significant contributing cause in hard cases. Butt contends that such a charge would be more consistent with how juries are actually instructed when evaluating causation: to ask themselves, “Did the accused contribute significantly to the victim’s death?” [109]

In complicated cases with either multiple contributing causes or intervening acts, courts routinely hold that the ultimate causation question is whether the accused contributed significantly to the victim’s death—an inquiry that places greater importance on the requisite strength of the accused’s contribution to a result as opposed to a counterfactual assessment about their involvement. [110]

III. Rethinking Intervening Acts and Legal Causation

Conceptions of legal causation in Canadian criminal law similarly require rethinking. The doctrine of independent intervening acts applies only in restricted circumstances and has largely been overshadowed by the doctrine of reasonably foreseeable intervening acts. The latter remains useful and is distinct from the foreseeability inquiry under mens rea; it serves to limit criminal liability where unforeseeable contributing causes fall outside the ambit of risk associated with the accused’s initial conduct.

A.  The Limited Role of Independent Intervening Acts in Canadian Law

The Supreme Court of Canada has alluded to different decisions as examples of judges employing the doctrine of independent intervening acts. In Maybin , the Court cited Shilon (the car-chase case) and Hallett (the rising tide case) as examples where courts maintained legal causation because the intervening act was not independent. [111] However, those decisions are unhelpful in illuminating the doctrine of independent intervening acts because they were resolved on the basis of the intervening act’s reasonable foreseeability.

Due to a combination of factors, the independent intervening act doctrine has been interpreted restrictively by Canadian courts compared to the doctrine of reasonably foreseeable intervening acts. Those same factors also account for why the doctrine of reasonably foreseeable intervening acts has largely overshadowed the doctrine of independent intervening acts.

First, Canadian courts tend to recognize that the victim’s own voluntary, deliberate, and informed conduct does not constitute an independent intervening act that breaks legal causation. [112] This is most notably the case where the victim dies after consuming drugs or some other harmful substance that the accused provided. In the Manitoba Court of Appeal decision R. v. Haas (CJ) , the accused gave the victim morphine pills. [113] She consumed the pills and died of a drug overdose. Haas was convicted of unlawful act manslaughter. The Court of Appeal upheld the conviction. The judges concluded that the accused’s conduct was an instrumental and significant cause of death, notwithstanding the victim’s voluntary decision to consume the drugs. [114] Other Canadian courts have arrived at the same conclusion in similar cases. [115]

The doctrine of independent intervening acts plays a greater role in England and other jurisdictions, where courts hold that the victim’s voluntary, informed, and deliberate conduct can sever causation. [116] In the UK House of Lords decision R. v. Kennedy , the defendant was a drug dealer who provided the victim with an opioid-filled syringe. [117] The victim injected the substance into his arm and died of a drug overdose. The defendant was convicted at trial of manslaughter, and the conviction was upheld by the Court of Appeal. The House of Lords substituted an acquittal, concluding that the victim’s autonomous act broke the causal chain. [118] By rejecting Kennedy ’s application in Canada, Canadian courts have largely restricted the use of the independent intervening acts doctrine. [119]

Second, certain Criminal Code provisions and common law rules restrict the application of independent intervening acts as an analytical tool. The victim’s refusal to receive life-saving care does not constitute an independent intervening act [120] —and neither does a third party’s good faith, although improper, medical treatment applied to a victim injured by the accused. [121]

Third, the criminal law’s rejection of contributory negligence and apportionment of liability also confines the doctrine of independent intervening acts. [122] This analytical tool serves to absolve the accused of responsibility only where a third party’s conduct or the victim’s own act is deemed to be the sole legal cause of the latter’s death. [123]

In Canadian criminal law, the doctrine of independent acts is generally subsumed by the test for reasonably foreseeable intervening acts. When courts inquire whether an independent act severs causation because its occurrence is extraordinary, they are inquiring whether the act is reasonably foreseeable. [124] The latter analytical tool will generally do the necessary legwork. The same is true where the accused’s conduct sets the scene for a third party’s assault, making the latter’s act the exclusive legal cause of the victim’s death. [125] In such contexts, the criminal law withholds the defendant’s liability for the victim’s death due to concerns about fair attribution.

Like in ordinary life, the criminal law recognizes that defendants exert meaningful control over their own conduct and its potential risks. An accused tends to exert less control, however, over others’ autonomous acts and the sphere of risks that others create. [126] When the general nature of others’ acts and their inherent risks are unforeseeable and too removed from the defendant’s autonomous conduct, those acts are deemed to be independent. In such cases, the harm that claims the victim’s life falls within an unanticipated sphere of risk that is more properly attributable to someone other than the accused. Here too, an analysis of the act’s independence collapses into an inquiry into its reasonable foreseeability. In other words, when assessing the general nature of the novus actus , courts evaluate whether something about the intervening act—its likelihood, type, scope, temporal remoteness, or surprising nature—undermines the intervening act’s reasonable foreseeability.

B.  Why Reasonably Foreseeable Intervening Acts Matter for Causation

The doctrine of reasonably foreseeable intervening acts plays a more prominent role in assessing legal causation within Canadian criminal law. This section argues that the doctrine’s purpose is distinct from the reasonable foreseeability inquiry as part of mens rea . It shows why an intervening act’s reasonable foreseeability acts as a heuristic (or rule of thumb) that is used to assess whether an ambit of risk can be fairly ascribed to the accused.

In Maybin , the Supreme Court of Canada observed that the analytical tool of reasonably foreseeable intervening acts closely aligns with the mens rea for manslaughter. [127] Yet to distinguish causation from the moral fault requirement for that crime, the Court held that the general nature of the intervening act and its accompanying risk of harm must be reasonably foreseeable at the time of the accused’s unlawful conduct. [128] As Justice Karakatsanis explained, causation generally remains intact where the intervening act and accompanying harm reasonably flow from the accused’s conduct. [129]

Butt argues that it is redundant to analyze the reasonable foreseeability of intervening acts because mens rea already requires proof of objective foresight of bodily harm. [130] In his view, the causation analysis should remove moral fault considerations. [131] Rather, courts should resort to the independent act tool and examine whether the intervening act is so proximally remote that it overshadows the accused’s behaviour as the sole cause in law of the victim’s death. [132] Certain courts share a somewhat similar view, observing that reasonable foreseeability is generally associated with moral fault and should be kept separate from causation and actus reus. [133]

The doctrine of reasonably foreseeable intervening acts, however, plays a role that is distinct from foreseeability with respect to mens rea. As explained further below, it acts as a safety valve to prevent unfair labelling. The doctrine of reasonably foreseeable intervening acts assesses the relationship between the accused’s wrongful conduct and the victim’s death, even where the accused possesses sufficient moral fault. [134] The doctrine of reasonably foreseeable intervening acts provides a legal heuristic for evaluating whether a contributing cause fell within the ambit of risk inherent to the accused’s wrongful and dangerous behaviour. [135] The term “ambit of risk” does not merely allude to the reasonable foreseeability of the intensity of certain risks or the possibility of some result materializing. Rather, it also encompasses the origin of certain risks and the kind of risks that reasonably flow from one’s conduct in a given circumstance.

Where causation is a significant issue, most cases turn on the fact that the victim suffered greater harm because of an intervening act than they would have experienced without its occurrence. For instance, an unconscious victim left face down on the pavement is not subject to a risk of drowning. An unconscious victim left face down on a beach and submerged in water (like in Hallett ) is subject to that added risk. In a similar vein, one-on-one fights in an isolated setting do not create additional risks that others will become involved and unfairly gang up on the victim. As was the case in Maybin , barfights do create that added risk. Intervening acts matter because the additional risks that those acts generate are often the difference between life and death. The scope of risk is therefore greater where the accused’s unlawful conduct exposes the victim to additional contributory sources of harm that otherwise would not arise.

Legal causation assesses whether additional contributory causes fall within the range of risks associated with the accused’s conduct and are therefore fairly ascribable to them. [136] In some contexts, unchosen and completely unforeseeable intervening causes play the predominant role in the victim’s death. Those contributory causes fall outside of the ambit of risk attributable to the accused. Such cases create a logical gap between the sphere of risk created by the accused’s behaviour and some tragic result.

Where such logical gaps are formed, the doctrine of reasonably foreseeable intervening acts withholds blaming the accused for the victim’s death due to fairness concerns related to both culpability and punishment. When the intervening act was unchosen, unforeseeable, and outside the scope of risks that flow from the accused’s conduct, it is difficult to justify punishing them for causing the victim’s death on the basis of desert or deterrence principles. [137] The upshot is that it is fairer to blame and punish defendants for reasonably foreseeable contributing causes that fall within the range of risks that they create. Legal causation recognizes that although defendants lack control over the consequences of creating a certain sphere of risk, they maintain greater control over their initial creation.

Legal causation—and the doctrine of reasonably foreseeable intervening acts—thus corrects for potential unfair blaming practices in the criminal law. [138] For instance, an accused’s dangerous and unlawful act might create a reasonably foreseeable risk of bodily harm. That very act may cause minor injuries to the victim. Suppose the victim decides to go to the hospital by ambulance as a precautionary measure. The ambulance is struck by a reckless driver and the victim dies. Causation ensures that the accused is not blamed for causing the victim’s death despite the fact that their act could have led to the same result. [139] Legal causation recognizes that an unforeseeable car accident caused by a reckless driver is a contributory cause that falls outside the realm of risk created by the accused’s initial assault—the doctrine excludes the accused’s conduct as an instrumentally salient cause of death.

In this way, legal causation acts as an additional fairness constraint that promotes fair labelling, especially in contexts where the accused satisfies a low-level mens rea requirement. [140] Cause in law blocks tempting, but inappropriate, desert-based inferential reasoning where the accused possessed sufficiently reprehensible mens rea. As an ascriptive constraint, it counteracts the enticement to attribute bad outcomes to the accused based on intuitions about what they deserve given their moral fault. Legal causation excludes ascribing certain results to the accused where their culpable and wrongful acts are simply a condition but not an instrumental and salient legal cause of the victim’s death. [141] The doctrine of reasonably foreseeable intervening acts affirms that certain unforeseeable contributing causes are not fairly ascribable to the accused because they fall outside the sphere of risk created by their conduct.

IV. Causation and Fair Attribution

The previous Parts highlighted certain limitations to the Supreme Court of Canada’s conceptions of factual causation, legal causation, and intervening acts. Building on Andrew Simester’s work, this Part provides an account of causation that is rooted primarily in the notions of attribution and fair labelling, as opposed to moral innocence. [142] It shows how attribution is concerned with connecting negative changes in the world and the creation of certain risks to some individuals at the exclusion of others. [143] Having set out that account, it then challenges the Supreme Court of Canada’s rationale for causation as necessary to prevent the conviction of morally innocent persons.

A.  Factual Causation: An Ascriptive Approach

In Nette , Justice Arbour observed that factual causation “is concerned with an inquiry about how the victim came to his or her death, in a medical, mechanical, or physical sense, and with the contribution of the accused to that result.” [144] Later, in Maybin , the Court added that factual causation is inclusive in scope—it determines who can be deemed to have factually contributed to some result. [145]

One shortfall of that view is that it cannot provide an account of causation for omissions, whose hallmark is the defendant’s inaction or non-intervention in the face of a duty to act. [146] The lack of a physical act implies that the defendant does not, in any positive sense, medically, physically, or mechanically contribute to the victim’s death. [147] Yet the criminal law still recognizes causal relations between a defendant’s inaction and the victim’s worsened plight, such as a parent’s failure to feed their child, resulting in the child’s injury or death. [148] Scholars such as George Fletcher, Arthur Leavens, and John Kleinig argue that factual causation is grounded in the existence of some pre-existing duty that creates a form of reliance between the defendant and the victim, making the accused responsible in fact for the victim’s plight. [149] The nature of the relationship between accused and victim is at the root of causation. [150] The notion of duties to act recognizes that defendants are responsible both for actions that intrude upon another’s interests as well as for inactions that deprive others of their interests. [151] Factual causation therefore must be concerned with something more than physical, medical, or mechanical contributions to results.

One way of addressing that shortfall is by thinking about factual causation in terms of ascription —the practice of attributing changes that take place in the world to particular individuals. Factual causation is largely concerned with tying events or states of affairs to individuals, be it through their actions or inactions. It links an individual to the changes that they effectuate in the world and that are properly attributable to them. [152] In the realm of criminal law, defendants’ conduct characteristically effectuates changes that worsen the victim’s plight or creates unreasonable risks to others. [153] As a heuristic used to draw inferences between conduct and outcomes, factual causation assesses whether some individual’s conduct is responsible for causing states of affairs to change for the worse. [154] Legal causation serves to ascribe prima facie moral responsibility in the form of a connection between the actor’s conduct and negative changes, to the exclusion of other persons . [155] For that reason, Simester observes that factual causation acts as a form of “boundary rule.” [156]

The more significant the accused’s contribution to some state of affairs, the greater the connection (or the stronger the inference) between their conduct and negative changes that occur in the world. Factual causation thus requires the state to provide a public account of why that individual is being singled out as a subject of potential criminal liability. The cause in fact inquiry answers one of the most basic questions at the heart of criminal liability: Why me ?

B.  Legal Causation and Fair Attribution

In Canadian law, courts justify legal causation primarily on the basis that it prevents the conviction of morally innocent persons. That rationale was first advanced in the Ontario Court of Appeal decision R. v. Cribbin and was later affirmed in Nette and Maybin . [157] In Cribbin , Justice Arbour explained:

I refer to the link between causation and the fault element in crime, represented in homicide by foresight of death or bodily harm, whether subjective or objective, because it serves to confirm that the law of causation must be considered to be a principle of fundamental justice akin to the doctrine of mens rea . The principle of fundamental justice which is at stake in the jurisprudence dealing with the fault element in crime is the rule that the morally innocent should not be punished. [158]

Justice Arbour reiterated that position in Nette , where she observed:

Legal causation, which is also referred to as imputable causation, is concerned with the question of whether the accused person should be held responsible in law for the death that occurred. It is informed by legal considerations such as the wording of the section creating the offence and principles of interpretation. These legal considerations, in turn, reflect fundamental principles of criminal justice such as the principle that the morally innocent should not be punished. [159]

The Supreme Court of Canada unanimously endorsed that statement in Maybin , observing that “[a]ny assessment of legal causation should maintain focus on whether the accused should be held legally responsible for the consequences of his actions, or whether holding the accused responsible for the death would amount to punishing a moral innocent.” [160] The argument that legal causation is necessarily justified by the need to prevent the conviction of morally innocent persons, however, is problematic for several reasons.

First, it ignores contexts where courts concede that the accused contributed to the victim’s death but withhold blame for that result nonetheless. Consider the following hypothetical. [161] Suppose that the accused intentionally causes low-level, objectively foreseeable bodily harm to the victim. [162] The victim is subsequently transported to a hospital for precautionary treatment. The ambulance is involved in a car accident and the victim dies. The accused’s dangerous and unlawful act was a significant factual contribution to the victim’s eventual death, meaning that the accused shares some responsibility for its occurrence. Yet because the accused only caused low-level bodily harm and the range of risk created by their conduct did not encompass a car accident, it is unjust to blame them for that death. [163]

In such cases, the law does not construe the accused as morally innocent, especially if they intended to cause bodily harm and succeeded. [164] Rather, it concedes the accused’s culpable contribution to the victim’s death but withholds blame for reasons more closely tied to the principles of attribution and fair labelling. [165] As described by Antony Duff, the core problem with blaming the accused for death in such contexts is not that the accused is innocent, but that they are “not that guilty.” [166] Fair labelling is violated where the accused is punished for something other than what they did or caused, because they are wrongly blamed for conduct or consequences that are not fairly attributable to them. [167] Legal causation therefore acts as a moral constraint that legitimates blaming practices in the criminal law. It draws a boundary between moral fault and attribution of results to individuals. [168]

Second, the need to protect morally innocent persons from conviction and punishment is generally rooted in incapacity or lack of moral fault. Various criminal law doctrines illustrate this point. [169] In Reference Re B.C. Motor Vehicle Act , the Supreme Court of Canada recognized a principle of fundamental justice that absolute liability offences cannot be combined with imprisonment. [170] Chief Justice Lamer explained that the provision in question was problematic because morally innocent individuals could be convicted and punished despite their due diligence, accident, or mistake of fact—all of which suggest a lack of moral fault. [171] Capacity-based concerns underlie the requisite degree of fault for objective mens rea . [172] Individuals must at least have the capacity to appreciate the risks inherent to their conduct to satisfy the objective standard of fault. [173] These criminal law doctrines generally aim to prevent the conviction of the morally innocent on the basis of physical or mental incapacity, or on the basis of a lack of moral fault.

Causation, on the other hand, is more concerned with fair attribution and accepts the defendant’s capacity and culpable state of mind. [174] Yet blame is withheld for an entirely different reason: that it is unfair to blame the accused for harms, risks, or consequences that are not ascribable to them. [175] As Simester explains:

Rather than culpability, the primary role of a finding of causation concerns ascriptive responsibility. It identifies D as an author of the relevant event. In turn, the primary legal role of causation is to identify defendants (and plaintiffs) and, where appropriate, to link defendants to plaintiffs, victims, and harms. [176]

Third, much like legal causation, other criminal law doctrines affirm that actors may act culpably but that it is unjust to blame and punish them due to concerns about fair attribution, rather than moral innocence. In R. v. Ruzic , the Supreme Court of Canada recognized that the basis of excuses is moral involuntariness and not moral innocence. [177] The Court explained that it would be unjust to attribute criminal responsibility to defendants who culpably commit crimes under duress. [178] In the Court’s view, moral involuntariness undermines fair attribution—a principle that is distinct from moral innocence. [179] Thus, when the accused is excused under the doctrine of duress, conviction and punishment are inappropriate despite blameworthy conduct. [180] The causation requirement is more plausibly justified by similar rationales that acknowledge fault but withhold blame.

Comparable concerns animate blaming practices for inchoate offences, where the accused does not successfully commit the crime or produce certain harms, as is the case for attempts and conspiracy. Sanford Kadish remarks that criminal law differentiates between blame for complete versus incomplete acts and materialized versus unmaterialized harms; [181] for inchoate offences, fair labelling recognizes the ascriptive connection between a person’s act and the completeness of that act or outcome. [182]

Cause in law thus acknowledges that an individual’s conduct significantly contributed to effectuating negative changes in the world. But it does not inquire specifically whether the harm that flowed from the accused’s conduct was reasonably foreseeable—a question that falls more within mens rea . Rather, legal causation assesses whether an additional contributing cause can fairly be ascribed to the accused because it fell within the ambit of risk generated by their initial wrongful conduct. [183] Thus, while factual causation ties changes in the world to individuals, legal causation ascribes scopes of risk to those individuals. Cause in law strives to answer a fundamental question rooted in fidelity to fair labelling practices: Why am I being blamed for this ?

This article advances an account of causation rooted in principles of ascription and fair labelling. It challenges the Supreme Court of Canada’s conception of factual and legal causation and their underlying rationales. It argues that causation is less concerned with avoiding the conviction of morally innocent individuals than with fairly attributing changes in the world and scopes of risk to some individuals while excluding others. The need to prove causation imposes a duty on the state to provide an account of why X (and not someone else) is blamed for Y (and not something else) . To that end, factual causation assesses whether one’s conduct significantly contributes to worsening the victim’s situation. Legal causation then evaluates whether individuals—including those with sufficient moral fault—can be fairly blamed for the materialization of risks that are properly ascribable to them.

This article admittedly leaves some questions unanswered—questions that most certainly merit to be explored in the near future. Most notably, one might inquire whether we should simply do away with the distinction between factual and legal causation altogether. As some judicial decisions point out, the ultimate causation question might be whether the accused contributed significantly to the result—an approach that is consistent with how juries ought to be instructed when causation is a live issue. [184] If that is the case, then why distinguish between factual and legal causation at all? Insofar as the answer to that question is more rooted in a commitment to experience rather than logic, it may be time to seriously reconsider our approach to causation in the criminal law altogether. [185] Yet it is also unclear whether a unified approach to causation—one that merges both factual and legal causation—will truly provide a more coherent path forward.

Indeed, like so many other complex areas of human life, we struggle to understand how things come to be and what our role is in effectuating changes in the world. In many respects, the law of causation, as well as the elusive attempt to simplify its principles and avoid mistakes, reflects this challenge. Although causation within the criminal law marks a noble attempt to fairly single out actors for changing others’ lives for the worse, it remains a heuristic that is itself vulnerable to constant questioning, criticism, and potential error. Like the human beings subject to its principles, causation in the law remains imperfect.

                       

[1]     See R v Maybin , 2012 SCC 24 at para 15 [ Maybin ]; R v Nette , 2001 SCC 78 at para 44 [ Nette ].

[2]     See Nette , supra note 1 at para 45, citing Glanville Williams, Textbook of Criminal Law , 2nd ed (London, UK: Stevens & Sons, 1983) at 381–82. See also Maybin , supra note 1 at paras 15–16; Larry Alexander, “Michael Moore and the Mysteries of Causation in the Law” (2011) 42:2 Rutgers LJ 301 at 301–02.

[3]     See e.g. Maybin , supra note 1.

[4]     See e.g. R v Hallett (1969), SASR 141 (SA Sup Ct) [ Hallett ].

[5]     See e.g. R v Reid , 2003 NSCA 104.

[6]     See e.g. R v   Blaue ,   [1975] EWCA Crim 3, [1975] 1 WLR 1411 (CA) [ Blaue ]; R v Tower , 2008 NSCA 3 [ Tower ]. See also Olga Redko, “Religious Practice as a ‘Thin Skull’ in the Context of Civil Liability” (2014) 72:1 UT Fac L Rev 38 at 52–53, 66–67.

[7]     See Glanville Williams, “Finis for Novus Actus ? ” (1989) 48:3 Cambridge LJ 391 at 391.

[8]     See Douglas Husak, “Abetting a Crime” (2014) 33:1 Law & Phil 41 at 68–71; Terry Skolnik, “Responsibility and Intervening Acts: What ‘ Maybin ’ an Overbroad Approach to Causation” (2014) 44:2 RGD 557 at 567. On the notion of moral luck, see Thomas Nagel, Mortal Questions (Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press, 1979) ch 3.

[9]     On the relationship between fault and stigma, see Kent Roach, “Mind the Gap: Canada’s Different Criminal and Constitutional Standards of Fault” (2011) 61:4 UTLJ 545 at 546, 556–59, 566–67.

[10]    See R v Wallace , [2018] EWCA Crim 690 at para 52 [ Wallace ]; Russell Brown, “The Possibility of ‘Inference Causation’: Inferring Cause-in-Fact and the Nature of Legal Fact-Finding” (2010) 55:1 McGill LJ 1 at 33.

[11]    See Fleming James Jr & Roger F Perry, “Legal Cause” (1951) 60:5 Yale LJ 761 at 763; Husak, supra note 8 at 66–71.

[12]    See Jeremy Butt, “Removing Fault from the Law of Causation” (2018) 65 Crim LQ 72 at 80–83.

[13]    See ibid at 89–90 .

[14]    See Nette , supra note 1 at para 45; Maybin , supra note 1 at paras 16, 57, 59.

[15]    On fair labelling, see AJ Ashworth, “The Elasticity of Mens Rea ” in CFH Tapper, ed, Crime, Proof and Punishment: Essays in Memory of Sir Rupert Cross (London, UK: Butterworths & Co, 1981) 45 at 53–56.

[16]    See David Ormerod & Karl Laird, eds, Smith, Hogan, and Ormerod’s Criminal Law , 15th ed (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2018) at 29.

[17]    Don Stuart, Canadian Criminal Law , 7th ed (Toronto: Carswell, 2014) at 142.

[18]    See ibid .

[19]    See Alexander, supra note 2 at 301.

[20]    See ibid.

[21]    Nette , supra note 1 at para 44.

[22]    See James & Perry, supra note 11 at 762–63.

[23]    See Smithers v R (1977), [1978] 1 SCR 506 at 518, 75 DLR (3d) 321 [ Smithers ].

[24]    See The Honourable S Casey Hill, David M Tanovich & Louis P Strezos, McWilliams’ Canadian Criminal Evidence , 5th ed (Toronto: Thompson Reuters, 2019) vol 2 at 12:30.60.10. See e.g. Smithers , supra note 23; R v Shanks (1996), 4 CR (5th) 79 at para 10, 1996 CanLII 2080 (ONCA) [ Shanks ]; R v Pimentel , 2000 MBCA 35 at para 63.

[25]    See Michael Moore, “Causation in the Criminal Law” in John Deigh & David Dolinko, eds, The Oxford Handbook of Philosophy of Criminal Law (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2011) 168 at 170–71. See e.g. R v Sinclair (T) , 2009 MBCA 71 at para 38 [ Sinclair ], rev’d on other grounds 2011 SCC 40.

[26]    Supra note 23 at 519.

[27]    Ibid .

[28]    See David Ormerod & Karl Laird, eds, Smith and Hogan’s Criminal Law , 14th ed (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2015) at 91–92.

[29]    See HLA Hart & Tony Honoré, Causation in the Law , 2nd ed (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1985) at 172–73 (the authors use the alternate term “eggshell skull”). See e.g. Athey v Leonati , [1996] 3 SCR 458 at paras 34–35, 140 DLR (4th) 235. The thin skull principle was entrenched in the common law and recognized by scholars such as Hale and Stephen: see Sir Matthew Hale, Historia Placitorum Coronae: The History of the Pleas of the Crown (London, UK: Nutt & Gosling, 1736) vol 1 at 428; Sir James Fitzjames Stephen, A History of the Criminal Law of England (London, UK: MacMillan & Co, 1883) vol 3 at 5–7. Stephen, however, cautioned that causation would be negated where the relationship between the defendant’s act and the consequence was too “obscure” ( ibid at 3).

[30]    See Dennis Klimchuk, “Causation, Thin Skulls and Equality” (1998) 11:1 Can JL & Jur 115 at 124 [Klimchuk, “Thin Skulls”]; M Anne Stalker, “Chief Justice Dickson’s Principles of Criminal Law” (1991) 20:2 Man LJ 308 at 309–11.

[31]    See e.g. Nette , supra note 1 at para 79.

[32]    See ibid at para 49.

[33]    Ibid at para 71. Many courts suggest that the significance of the defendant’s contribution to the result is part of factual rather than legal causation (see e.g. R v Kippax , 2011 ONCA 766 at para 24 [ Kippax ]; Cormier c R , 2019 QCCA 76 at para 16; R v Romano , 2017 ONCA 837 at paras 27–28; Sarazin c R , 2018 QCCA 1065 at para 21). This article adopts that position. Some decisions, however, suggest that an intervening act cancels the significance of the defendant’s contribution to a result, which seems to suggest that the significance of the defendant’s contribution to a result is part of legal rather than factual causation (see e.g. Maybin , supra note 1 at paras 5, 29). Lastly, other decisions seem to suggest that the ultimate question that both factual and legal causation must address is whether the defendant contributed significantly to the result, making it unclear whether the significance of the contribution is part of factual or legal causation (see e.g. R v Talbot , 2007 ONCA 81 at para 81 [ Talbot ]; Sinclair , supra note 25 at para 39).

[34]    See Nette , supra note 1 at para 71 .

[35]    See ibid at para 72. Some scholars have also argued that the term “beyond the de minimis range” is not fixed, but depends on the circumstances of the case: see e.g. Hillel David, W Paul McCague & Peter F Yaniszewski, “Proving Causation Where the But For Test is Unworkable” (2005) 30:2 Adv Q 216 at 223.

[36]    See Maybin , supra note 1 at para 16; Eric Colvin, “Causation in Criminal Law” (1989) 1:2 Bond L Rev 253 at 254.

[37]    See Tower , supra note 6 at para 25 (cited with approval in Maybin , supra note 1 at para 23).

[38]    See Sanford H Kadish, “Complicity, Cause and Blame: A Study in the Interpretation of Doctrine” (1985) 73:2 Cal L Rev 323 at 407 [Kadish, “Complicity, Cause and Blame”].

[39]    See Criminal Code , RSC 1985, c C-46, ss 222(5)(c), 224, 225, 226.

[40]    See ibid , s 224.

[41]    See Tower , supra note 6 at para 31 (manslaughter conviction upheld despite the victim’s refusal of medical care after being injured by the accused, who had attacked him with long-handed pruning shears); R c Gosselin , 2011 QCCQ 7696 [ Gosselin ] (manslaughter conviction entered where the victim was stabbed by the accused and refused to go the hospital); Blaue , supra note 6 at 1414–15 (causation maintained despite the victim’s refusal of a blood transfusion on religious grounds).

[42]    See Criminal Code , supra note 39, s 225.

[43]    See s upra note 1 at para 5.

[44]    See ibid at paras 30–44; Jonathan Herring, Criminal Law: Text, Cases, and Materials , 6th ed (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2014) at 124–26, citing Klimchuk, “Thin Skulls”, supra note 30 at 129–35.

[45]    See Maybin , supra note 1 at paras 45–59.

[46]    S upra note 4 at 155.

[47]    For a similar decision, see R v Hart , [1986] 2 NZLR 408 (CA).

[48]    (2006), 240 CCC (3d) 401, [2006] OJ 4896 (QL) (Ont CA).

[49]    See ibid at para 41 .

[50]    See ibid at paras 38–39 .

[51]    See Maybin , supra note 1 at para 27, citing R v Pagett , [1983] EWCA Crim 1 [ Pagett ].

[52]    See Maybin , supra note 1 at para 50.

[53]    See ibid at para 51.

[54]    See ibid.

[55]    See Gerry Ferguson, “Causation and the Mens Rea for Manslaughter: A Lethal Combination” (2013) 99 CR (6th) 351 at 351–53.

[56]    See Maybin , supra note 1 at para 57; R v Leroux , 2018 BCSC 1429 at para 44 [ Leroux ].

[57]    See Nette , supra note 1 at para 72.

[58]    Ibid.

[59]    See Stanley Yeo, “Giving Substance to Legal Causation” (2000) 29 CR (5th) 215 at 218–20.

[60]    Ibid at 219 .

[61]    Nette , supra note 1 at para 7.

[62]    See Hugues Parent, Traité de droit criminel, t 2, 2nd ed (Montreal: Thémis, 2007) at para 74.

[63]    See e.g. ibid ; Jill Presser, “All for a Good Cause: The Need for Overhaul of the Smithers Test of Causation” (1994) 28 CR (4th) 178 at 178–83, cited in Stuart, Canadian Criminal Law , supra note 17 at 151.

[64]    Presser, supra note 63 at 183.

[65]    David M Tanovich & James Lockyer, “Revisiting Harbottle: Does the ‘Substantial Cause’ Test Apply to All Murder Offences?” (1996) 38:3 Crim LQ 322 at 332. See also R v F(D) (1989), 52 CCC (3d) 357 at 365, ( sub nom R v DLF ) 1989 ABCA 286 (CanLII).

[66]    See Anne-Marie Boisvert, “La responsabilité versant acteurs : vers une redécouverte, en droit canadien, de la notion d’imputabilité” (2003) 33:2 RGD 271 at 288.

[67]    See ibid.

[68]    See ibid . See also Nette , supra note 1 at para 49.

[69]    See Law Reform Commission of Canada, Report on Recodifying Criminal Law , Report 31 (Ottawa: Law Reform Commission of Canada, 1987) at 28, cited in Donald Galloway, “Causation in Criminal Law: Interventions, Thin Skulls and Lost Chances” (1989) 14:1 Queen’s LJ 71 at 80. Note that Galloway disagrees with the Law Reform Commission’s definition of the causation standard.

[70]    See s upra note 69 at 28 .

[71]    See Don Stuart, “ Nette : Confusing Cause in Reformulating the Smithers Test” (2002) 46 CR (5th) 230 at 230–31 [Stuart, “Confusing Cause”].

[72]    Supra note 24.

[73]    See ibid at para 8 .

[74]    See Stuart , “Confusing Cause”, supra note 71 at 230–31.

[75]    See Glanville Williams, “Convictions and Fair Labelling” (1983) 42:1 Cambridge LJ 85 at 85.

[76]    See Joseph J Arvay & Alison M Latimer, “The Constitutional Infirmity of the Laws Prohibiting Criminal Negligence” (2016) 63 Crim LQ 324 at 344.

[77]    See Criminal Code , supra note 39, ss 220, 236.

[78]    See generally Lawrence M Solan, “Law, Language, and Lenity” (1998) 40:1 Wm & Mary L Rev 57 at 58; Stephen Kloepfer, “The Status of  Strict Construction   in   Canadian Criminal Law” (1983) 15:3 Ottawa L Rev 553 at 553 . For an overview of lenity in criminal law, see Kent Roach, Criminal Law , 7th ed (Toronto: Irwin Law, 2018) at 92, 100, 102.

[79]    See William J Stuntz, “The Pathological Politics of Criminal Law” (2001) 100:3 Mich L Rev 505 at 561.

[80]    See R v Hasselwander , [1993] 2 SCR 398 at 411–13, 81 CCC (3d) 471.

[81]    See Glanville Williams, Criminal Law: The General Part , 2nd ed (London, UK: Stevens & Sons, 1961) at 588–89.

[82]    See Livingston Hall, “Strict or Liberal Construction of Penal Statutes” (1935) 48:5 Harv L Rev 748 at 763–64; Zachary Price, “The Rule of Lenity as a Rule of Structure” (2004) 72:4 Fordham L Rev 885 at 912–25; Peter Westen, “Two Rules of Legality in Criminal Law” (2007) 26:3 Law & Phil 229 at 281–83.

[83]    See e.g. R v Mankda, 2017 ONSC 5745 at para 19; R v Boffa, 2018 BCSC 768 at para 80; R v Bridle , 2007 BCSC 1100 at paras 24–25 (all using the beyond de minimis range test). See also the review of the trial judge’s instructions in Sinclair , supra note 25 at paras 22, 42. Other courts hold that judges may employ either the beyond the de minimis range test or the significant contributing cause test: see e.g. R v Harvey , 2016 BCCA 149 at para 20.

[84]    See supra note 1 at para 72.

[85]    See Maybin , s upra note 1 at paras 5, 7, 23, 28, 29, 38, 44, 59–61.

[86]    See e.g. Wallace , supra note 10 at para 64.

[87]    See e.g. R v Manasseri , 2016 ONCA 703 at paras 81–82 [ Manasseri ].

[88]    See Maybin , supra note 1 at para 15.

[89]    See ibid at para 20; R v Haas (CJ) , 2016 MBCA 42 at para 47 [ Haas ]; R v McDonald , 2017 ONCA 568 at para 139 [ McDonald ]; Manasseri , supra note 87 at para 189.

[90]    See Butt, supra note 12 at 89–90.

[91]    Ernest J Weinrib, “A Step Forward in Factual Causation” (1975) 38:5 Mod L Rev 518 at 522.

[92]    See David, McCague & Yaniszewski, supra note 35 at 219; Clements v Clements , 2012 SCC 32 at para 40. It is important to note that the Supreme Court of Canada did not adopt a significant contributing cause test in Clements , but rather settled on a standard of significant contribution to the risk of harm ( ibid at para 15).

[93]    See Butt, supra note 12 at 89–90; Michael S Moore, Causation and Responsibility: An Essay in Law, Morals, and Metaphysics (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2009) at 404 [Moore, Causation and Responsibility ].

[94]    See Weinrib, supra note 91 at 521–22.  

[95]    See A Philip Dawid, “The Role of Scientific and Statistical Evidence in Assessing Causality” in Richard Goldberg, ed, Perspectives on Causation (Oxford: Hart, 2011) 133 at 134.

[96]    See Moore, Causation and Responsibility , supra note 93 at 396–99.

[97]    See Maybin , supra note 1 at paras 28–29, 60; Nette , supra note 1 at paras 71, 87.

[98]    See Butt, supra note 12 at 89–90.

[99]    (2002), 50 CR (5th) 343 at paras 1–3, 53 WCB (2d) 49.

[100] See ibid at para 4.

[101] See ibid at para 92.

[102] See ibid at para 102.

[103] See ibid at para 89.

[104] See ibid at para 105. See also R v Galloway (1957), 26 CR 342 at 343–44, [1957] OJ No 222 (QL) (Ont CA); R v Rotundo , [1991] OJ No 3489 (QL) at paras 40–44 (Ont Ct J), 1991 CarswellOnt 49 (WL Can); R v Kippax , supra note 33 at para 43.

[105] See e.g. R v JSR , 2008 ONCA 544 at paras 32–34.

[106] See Weinrib, supra note 91 at 522.   

[107] See ibid at 522–23.

[108] Ibid.

[109] See Butt, supra note 12 at 87–89. See also Nette , supra note 1 at para 46.

[110] See Maybin , supra note 1 at para 1; R v R (JS) , 2012 ONCA 568 at para 107; R v Hughes , [2013] UKSC 56 at para 22; Talbot , supra note 33 at para 81; Wallace , supra note 10 at para 64; Kate O’Hanlon, “ R v Dear ” [1996] Crim L Rev 595 at 595–96; R v Hughes , 2011 BCCA 220 at para 58; Manasseri , supra note 87 at paras 46, 49, 82; McDonald , supra note 89 at para 137.

[111] See Maybin , supra note 1 at paras 47–48.

[112] See e.g. Haas , supra note 89 at para 61; R v CW (2006), 209 OAC 1 at paras 5–6, [2006] OJ No 1392 (QL) (Ont CA) [ CW ]; R v Valiquette, 2017 NBQB 027 at para 203; R v Jordan (1991), 4 BCAC 121, 1991 CarswellBC 750 (WL Can) [ Jordan ]; R v Worrall (2004), 189 CCC (3d) 79 at paras 231, 234, 244, 2004 CanLII 66306 (ONSC) [ Worrall ]; R v Tremblay , 2013 BCSC 816 at paras 98–99 [ Tremblay ]. The concept that a victim’s voluntary, deliberate, and informed conduct breaks causation was initially advanced by Hart & Honoré, supra note 29 at 326.

[113] Supra note 89 at para 14.

[114] See i bid at paras 63–64.

[115] See e.g. Jordan , supra note 112; CW , supra note 112; Worrall , supra note 112; Tremblay , supra  note 112 (all cited in Haas , supra note 89) .

[116] See generally Ian Dobinson, “Drug Supply, Self-Administration and Manslaughter: An Australian Perspective” (2011) J Australasian L Teachers Assoc 41 at 51.

[117] [2007] UKHL 38.

[118] See ibid at paras 16–18.

[119]   See e.g. Haas , supra note 89 at para 61.

[120] See Criminal Code , supra note 39, s 224; Tower , supra  note 6 at para 31; Gosselin , supra note 41 at paras 21–24; Blaue , supra note 6 at 1415.

[121] See Criminal Code , supra note 39, s 225; R v Lucas (2001), 156 CCC (3d) 474 at paras 82–83, 2001 CanLII 9533 (QCCA) (causation was upheld despite the possibility of negligent medical treatment by third parties); R v Malcherek , [1981] 1 WLR 690 at 697, [1981] 2 All ER 422 (causation was upheld where physicians disconnected life support); R v N(M) , 2004 NUCJ 1 at para 19 (causation was maintained where the victim died after physicians were instructed by family members not to supply medical treatment).

[122] See Nette , supra note 1 at para 49.

[123] See Maybin , supra note 1 at para 27; Pagett , supra note 51; Dunne v Director of Public Prosecutions , [2016] IESC 24 at para 70.

[124] See Maybin , supra note 1 at paras 31, 50.

[125] See ibid at para 50.

[126] See Hart & Honoré, supra note 29 at 326.

[127] See supra note 1 at para 36 .

[128] See ibid at para 38.

[129] See ibid .

[130] See Butt, supra note 12 at 85.

[131] See ibid.

[132] See ibid at 85–86 .

[133] See Sinclair , supra note 25 at para 47.

[134] See generally AP Simester & GR Sullivan, “Being There” (2012) 71:1 Cambridge LJ 29 at 30–31; AP Simester et al, eds, Simester and Sullivan’s Criminal Law: Theory and Doctrine, 6th ed (Oxford: Hart, 2016) at 92.

[135] On the notion of ambit of risk and causation, see George P Fletcher, “Prolonging Life” (1967) 42:4 Wash L Rev 999 at 1010; David Cheifetz, “Factual Causation in Negligence After Clements ” (2013) 41:2/3 Adv Q 179 at 262–72; Benjamin Snow, “A Cause for Concern: Incoherence in the Doctrine of Intervening Cause” (2012) 92 CR (6th) 241.

[136] See Alan Brudner, “Owning Outcomes: On Intervening Causes, Thin Skulls, and Fault-Undifferentiated Crimes” (1998) 11:1 Can JL & Jur 89 at 91.

[137] See generally Sanford H Kadish, “Foreword: The Criminal Law and the Luck of the Draw” (1994) 84:4 J Crim L & Criminology 679 at 688–95.

[138] See Andrew Summers, “Common-Sense Causation in the Law” (2018) 38:4 Oxford J Leg Stud 793 at 816–19.

[139] See Tanovich & Lockyer, supra note 65 at 331.

[140] See ibid.

[141] See Jonathan Schaffer, “Contrastive Causation” (2005) 114:3 Philosophical Rev 327 at 343.

[142] See AP Simester, “Causation in (Criminal) Law” (2017) 133 Law Q Rev 416 at 416–18.

[143] See generally Alan Norrie, “A Critique of Criminal Causation” (1991) 54 Mod L Rev 685 at 688–89.

[144] Supra note 1 at para 44.

[145] See supra note 1 at para 15.

[146] See Tony Honoré, Responsibility and Fault (Oxford: Hart, 1999) at 43. See generally Graham Hughes, “Criminal Omissions” (1958) 67:4 Yale LJ 590 at 636–37.

[147] See Honoré, supra note 146 at 50–51.

[148] See Criminal Code , supra note 39, s 215; George P Fletcher, “On the Moral Irrelevance of Bodily Movements” (1994) 142:5 U Pa L Rev 1443 at 1448 [Fletcher, “Moral Irrelevance”].

[149] See Fletcher, “Moral Irrelevance”, supra note 148; Arthur Leavens, “A Causation Approach to Criminal Omissions” (1988) 76:3 Cal L Rev 547 at 574–75; John Kleinig, “Criminal Liability for Failures to Act” (1986) 49:3 Law & Contemp Probs 161 at 161.

[150] See Fletcher, “Prolonging Life”, supra note 135 at 1006.

[151] See Honoré, supra note 146 at 50.

[152] See Stephen J Morse, “Reason, Results, and Criminal Responsibility” [2004] 2 U Ill L Rev 363 at 442; Honoré, supra note 146 at 52–53.

[153] See Morse, supra note 152 at 376–77. See also Honoré, supra note 146 at 53, 56.

[154] See Honoré, supra note 146 at 53, 56; Galloway, supra note 69 at 72.

[155] See AP Simester, “Why Omissions Are Special” (1995) 1 Leg Theory 311 at 328–29.

[156] “Causation in the (Criminal) Law”, supra note 142 at 421.

[157] See R v Cribbin (1994), 89 CCC (3d) 67 at 87, 1994 CanLII 391 (ONCA); Nette , supra note 1 at para 45; Maybin , supra note 1 at para 16. See also Leroux , supra note 56 at paras 40–41.

[158] Supra note 157 at 87.

[159] Supra note 1 at para 45.

[160] Supra note 1 at para 29.

[161] Similar hypotheticals are advanced by Stuart, Stapleton, Tanovich, Lockyer, and Morse. See Don Stuart, “Vagueness, Inconsistency and Less Respect for Charter Rights of Accused at the Supreme Court in 2012–2013” (2013) 63 SCLR (2d) 441 at 446 [Stuart, “Vagueness”]; Jane Stapleton, “Choosing What We Mean by ‘Causation’ in the Law” (2008) 73 Mo L Rev 433 at 461; Tanovich & Lockyer, supra note 65 at 331; Morse, supra note 152 at 396.

[162] See Stuart, “Vagueness”, supra note 161 at 446.

[163] See Morse, supra note 152 at 396–97.

[164] For a similar critique of the concept of moral innocence despite the existence of moral fault, see James Stribopoulos, “Constitutionalization of ‘Fault’ in Canada: A Normative Critique” (1999) 42 Crim LQ 227 at 257–58.

[165] See James Chalmers & Fiona Leverick, “Fair Labelling in Criminal Law” (2008) 71:2 Mod L Rev 217 at 218–20.

[166] The original quote by Antony Duff is “He is not innocent, but he is not that guilty; he is not punished for the offence which he committed” (RA Duff, Trials and Punishments (Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press, 1991) at 155).

[167] See Kleinig, supra note 149 at 169; Barry Mitchell, “Multiple Wrongdoing and Offence Structure: A Plea for Consistency and Fair Labelling” (2001) 64:3 Mod L Rev 393 at 398–99.

[168] See George P Fletcher, Rethinking Criminal Law (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2000) at §6.7.

[169] See generally Alan N Young, “Done Nothing Wrong: Fundamental Justice and the Minimum Content of Criminal Law” (2008) 40 SCLR (2d) 441 at 481–85.

[170] See Reference Re BC Motor Vehicle Act , [1985] 2 SCR 486 at 492, 24 DLR (4th) 536.

[171] See ibid at 519–20. See also R v Sault Ste Marie , [1978] 2 SCR 1299 at 1310, 85 DLR (3d) 161.

[172] See RA Duff, “Choice, Character, and Criminal Liability” (1993) 12:4 Law & Phil 345 at 350–54.

[173] See R v Creighton , [1993] 3 SCR 3 at 60–61, 105 DLR (4th) 632; R v Finlay , [1993] 3 SCR 103 at 115, 105 DLR (4th) 699; R v Roy , 2012 SCC 26 at paras 30–37.

[174] See HLA Hart, Punishment and Responsibility: Essays in the Philosophy of Law , 2nd ed (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2008) at 152–53; Colvin, supra note 36 at 263.

[175] See Fletcher, Rethinking Criminal Law , supra note 168 at §6.6.1.

[176] “Causation in the (Criminal) Law”, supra note 142 at 424.

[177] 2001 SCC 24 at paras 29–31, 40, 44–45 [ Ruzic ]. See also Fletcher, Rethinking Criminal Law , supra note 168 at §10.3.

[178] See Ruzic , supra note 177 at paras 40, 45.

[179] See ibid at paras 40–41; Dennis Klimchuk, “Moral Innocence, Normative Involuntariness, and Fundamental Justice” (1998) 18 CR (5th) 96 at 97–98; Benjamin L Berger, “Emotions and the Veil of Voluntarism: The Loss of Judgment in Canadian Criminal Defences” (2006) 51:1 McGill LJ 99 at 104–05.

[180] See Ruzic , supra note 177 at para 40; Terry Skolnik, “Three Problems with Duress and Moral Involuntariness” (2016) 63 Crim LQ 124 at 127.

[181] See Kadish, “Complicity, Cause and Blame”, supra note 38 at 356.

[182] See James Edwards & Andrew Simester, “Crime, Blameworthiness, and Outcomes” (2019) 39:1 Oxford J Leg Stud 50 at 71.

[183] See e.g . Sally Kyd, “Causing Death” in Alan Reed & Michael Bohlander, eds, Homicide in Criminal Law: A Research Companion (New York: Routledge, 2018) 119 at 134. As cited by Kyd, the concept of causal salience is advanced by Simester et al, supra note 134 at 92.  

[184] See e.g. Talbot , supra note 33 at para 81; Sinclair , supra note 25 at para 39. See also Canadian Judicial Council, “Model Jury Instructions” (2012) at D.6 (Offence 222(5): Unlawful Act Manslaughter), online (pdf): National Judicial Institute < www.nji-inm.ca> [perma.cc/2HEJ-3R9N]; Butt, supra note 12 at 87–88.

[185] See OW Holmes Jr, The Common Law (Boston: Little, Brown, and Company, 1881) at 1 (Holmes’ famous quote is “The life of the law has not been logic: it has been experience”).

Thank you to our sponsors

criminal law essay on causation

Causation in Criminal Liability and Reforms Essay

  • To find inspiration for your paper and overcome writer’s block
  • As a source of information (ensure proper referencing)
  • As a template for you assignment

Firstly, the causation in criminal liability implies the understanding of whether the defendant could be considered as a cause of the damage (Brody and Acker 115). In turn, it is divided into factual and legal causation (Bacigal and Tate 32). The core goal of this essay is to evaluate different types of causation and introduce reforms for improvement.

Factual causation implies that the damage could not have possibly occurred without the actions of the defendant (Bacigal and Tate 32). White’s case refers to the factual causation, as the defendant had the intention to murder his mother but was not the primary cause of it (“R v White” par. 1). Consequently, the law does not consider the necessity of punishment for the planning of the murder. In turn, Pagett’s case refers to the murder’s usage of the girl as a shield to protect himself from the fire (“R v Pagett ” par. 1). The police were the primary cause of the girls’ death, but it was considered as self-defense, and no factual causation was depicted. In turn, the law does not deliberate the possibility of the intervention of the third party.

In turn, the legal causation implies that the defendant’s conduct is punishable due to legal recognition (Bacigal and Tate 32). In this case, Kimsey’s case states that two girls were racing a car, and it led to the death of one girl (Ashbourne College par. 7). The legal causation implied that one was responsible for death due to the legal matters despite having two individuals involved in the accident. In turn, the Addams’ case is also contradictive as the doctor prescribed the medications and it led to the death of the patient (“Dr. Bodkins Adams” par. 1). In this instance, the law did not consider the professional duties, as Addams was convicted. Furthermore, the legal aspects do not consider the possibility of the involvement of multiple parties, as the examples are the case of Benge and the case of Marchent v Muntz (“Causation in Criminal Liability” par. 7).

The actions of the defendants were not the primary reasons for the damage. Additionally, Dear was found liable for the crime, as he attacked a person with a knife despite the possibility that the victim worsened his/her wounds himself/herself (Teal and Beauman 93). In this case, the law could not consider all angles of the situation. Furthermore, Roberts was convicted of grabbing a hitchhiker while jumping out of the car, was convicted of the crime, and this case portrayed the issue with daftness (Teal and Beauman 93). A similar case occurred with Williams, as the hitchhiker jumped out of the car, and Williams was convicted while not being guilty (Teal and Beauman 93). Lastly, the case of Cheshire explains that despite having the doctor’s fault, the defendant was still convicted due to the person’s death (“R v Cheshire” par. 1).

Based on the analysis of the cases provided above, the reforms have to be introduced to enhance justice in terms of legal decision-making. One of them is the ability to view each case individually and take into account the potential involvement of the third party. In turn, each case has to be considered from different perspectives. Lastly, the reform has to introduce a new system for the determination of the causation of the crimes while considering logic, factual, and legal causations simultaneously.

As for the evaluation of the reforms, they will contribute to equality in society. In turn, they will increase recognition and respect of the legal system in the society, and assist in the development of the logical foundations for the punishment. Nonetheless, the primary drawbacks of the individual approach are the subjectivity of the opinions and high time consumption for the decision-making.

Works Cited

Ashbourne College . Re: Law Blog: Causation. 2016. Web.

Bacigal, Ronald, and Mary Tate. Criminal Law and Procedure: An Overview , Stamford: Cengage Learning, 2015. Print.

Brody, David and James Acker. Criminal Law , Boston: Jones and Bartlett Publishers, 2010. Print.

Causation in Criminal Liability 2015. Web.

Dr Bodkins Adams 1957. Web.

R v Cheshire 1991. Web.

R v Pagett 1983. Web.

R v White 1910. Web.

Teal, Sue, and Craig Beauman. OCR Criminal Law and Special Study Paper , Abington: Hodder Education, 2013. Print.

  • Cybercrime Impact on Global Criminal Justice System
  • Corrupt Practices of the Police and Correctional Systems
  • Major Theories of Crime Causation
  • Crime Causation and Diversion in the Florida State
  • Women’s Family and Social Responsibilities and Rights
  • Identity Theft Crimes in the United States
  • Drug Control, Gun Policies, and Sex Offender Laws
  • Media Influence on Criminal Justice and Community
  • Police Issues and Practices Discussion
  • Louisiana’s Sentencing Model and Alternatives
  • Chicago (A-D)
  • Chicago (N-B)

IvyPanda. (2020, August 24). Causation in Criminal Liability and Reforms. https://ivypanda.com/essays/causation-in-criminal-liability-and-reforms/

"Causation in Criminal Liability and Reforms." IvyPanda , 24 Aug. 2020, ivypanda.com/essays/causation-in-criminal-liability-and-reforms/.

IvyPanda . (2020) 'Causation in Criminal Liability and Reforms'. 24 August.

IvyPanda . 2020. "Causation in Criminal Liability and Reforms." August 24, 2020. https://ivypanda.com/essays/causation-in-criminal-liability-and-reforms/.

1. IvyPanda . "Causation in Criminal Liability and Reforms." August 24, 2020. https://ivypanda.com/essays/causation-in-criminal-liability-and-reforms/.

Bibliography

IvyPanda . "Causation in Criminal Liability and Reforms." August 24, 2020. https://ivypanda.com/essays/causation-in-criminal-liability-and-reforms/.

IPSA LOQUITUR

Criminal Law: Causation

Factual causation, the ‘but for’ test.

Some crimes require the defendant to cause a particular result. If this is the case, the prosecution must prove factual and legal causation. Factual causation exists if but for the defendant’s act or omission, the result would not have come about: R v White [1910] 2 KB 124. The defendant’s acts do not to be the sole cause, or even the main cause, of the proscribed result: R v Hennigan [1971] 3 All ER 133.

Legal Causation

‘breaks in causation’.

Certain subsequent events may ‘break the chain of causation’ between the defendant’s action and the proscribed result. In these circumstances, the defendant is not taken to have caused the result in law.

Act of a Third Party

Car pile up

Reasonable or foreseeable third-party actions will not break causation: R v Pagett  (1983) 76 Cr App R 279. Completely unforeseeable acts, or fully informed, unreasonable and voluntary acts of third parties may break causation, however: R v Latif [1996] 2 Cr App r 92. Generally, the criminal law is far less willing than tort to find that the act of third parties (even negligent or deliberate acts) are unforeseeable or unreasonable: R v Benge (1865) 4 F&F 504; R v Warburton & Hubbersty [2006] EWCA Crim 627.

Act of the Claimant

Person rock climbing, dangerous

If the victim’s actions are a natural or foreseeable consequence of the defendant’s actions, they will not break causation: R v Roberts  [1971] EWCA Crim 4; R v Pitts (1842) Car & M 284. Only completely ‘daft’ or ‘unexpected’ actions in the circumstances will break causation: R v Williams & Davis [1992] Crim LR 198. Free, informed and voluntary actions of a capable victim (particularly in drug-taking cases) will break the chain of causation, however: R v Kennedy (No 2) [2007] UKHL 38. However, not even outright suicide will be ‘voluntary’ if the defendant’s actions provide a strong reason or compulsion for it: R v Wallace [2018] EWCA Crim 690.

Act of Nature

act of nature, lightning bolt

A completely unforeseeable non-human act may break the chain of causation if it is not a natural result of what the defendant did. For example, a defendant is a legal cause of death if he knocks the victim unconscious and leaves him in a puddle to drown, but not if the building the unconscious victim is left in subsequently collapses on his head for unrelated reasons: R v Hallet [1969] SASR 141.

The Eggshell Skull Rule

The defendant must take the victim as they find them. This has two implications:

The result does not need to be foreseeable. This means that if the claimant has a special condition that makes them more likely to suffer harm (or more serious harm) than a normal person, the defendant is still taken to cause the harm: R v Hayward (1908) 21 Cox 692.

When determining if the claimant’s acts break the chain of causation, actions which are due to the claimant’s particular beliefs, values or religious doctrines are unlikely to be considered completely daft or unexpected: R v Holland (1841) 2 Mood & R 351; R v Blaue [1975] 1 WLR 1411.

The Defendant’s Contribution Must be an ‘Operative’ Cause

If the defendant’s contribution is merely background setting, they are not a legal cause.

For example, the defendant invites the victim to his house. The victim is killed in a car accident on the way. The defendant is not a legal cause of death even though without their invitation the victim would be alive.

Making the distinction between operative and non-operative causes can be difficult and causes particular problems in negligent medical treatment cases:

For example, in R v Jordan   (1956) 40 Cr App E 152, the victim died of pneumonia more than a week after being stabbed by the defendant. At the time of death, the stab wounds had started to heal. The cause of the pneumonia was the negligent administration of fluids and antibiotics which the victim was allergic to. The defendant’s act was deemed not to be an operative cause of death.

By contrast, in R v Smith [1959] 2 QB 35, the defendant stabbed the victim. The victim was dropped several times on the way to receive medical treatment. The doctor then failed to properly diagnose the victim’s injuries, meaning he was not treated for a punctured lung. The victim probably would have survived if he had been given proper medical treatment. Nevertheless, the defendant was found to have caused his death since the victim died of the punctured lung.

In R v Cheshire [1991] 1 WLR 844, the defendant shot the victim in the leg and stomach. The victim developed respiratory problems in hospital and was given a tracheotomy as a result. He later died from complications from the tracheotomy, at a time when his shooting wounds were healing. The defendant’s shooting was deemed to be an operative cause of death. This was because the subsequent medical treatment was not ‘so potent’ that it made the defendant’s contribution unimportant.

The Cause Must Be ‘Culpable’

The act which the prosecution relies on as being the ’cause’ must be culpable: R v Dalloway (1847) 2 Cox CC 273. This does not mean that the defendant must have acted deliberately or negligently, merely that there is something about what the defendant did which was ‘open to proper criticism’: R v Hughes [2013] UKSC 56.

Basic Concepts of Criminal Law Quiz

Test yourself on the basic concepts of criminal law, including actus reus , mens rea and causation.

Harold is arrested when he is found in possession of a strange package. He is asked whether there are drugs inside, and he answers that it is very likely, but that he is not sure. The package turns out to be full of cocaine. What is Harold's state of mind with respect to the package?

Incorrect . If the crime states that the defendant must know or believe that something is the case, it is not enough that he merely has reason to believe it is the case or suspects it is the case.

The actus reus and mens rea of an offence do not need to coincide. True or false?

Incorrect . The defendant must have had a 'guilty mind' at the time the actus reus was being carried out: Criminal Injuries Compensation Authority v First-tier Tribunal.

If the defendant does the actus reus against one person, but had the mens rea with respect to another person, is this sufficient to show an offence?

Incorrect . The doctrine of transferred malice applies: R v Mitchell.

Battery is a crime of basic intent. True or false?

Incorrect . See R v Heard.

Rape is a crime of basic intent. True or false?

Incorrect . See R v Woods.

Assault is a crime of specific intent. True or false?

What must the prosecution prove to establish factual causation?

Incorrect . Factual causation exists if but for the defendant's act or omission, the result would not have come about: R v White . The defendant's acts do not to be the sole cause, or even the main cause, of the proscribed result: R v Hennigan.

Incorrect .

Lacy burns down a house for insurance money, knowing that Eric is inside, handcuffed to a bed and unable to escape. She claims she did not want Eric dead. However, she says she thought that it was very likely that he would die, as she cannot remember whether the key to the handcuffs was left close enough for Eric to reach. Did Lacey intend to kill Eric?

Incorrect . Lacey would need to think it was virtually certain that Eric would die, to have oblique intent to kill him: R v Woollin. She only thinks it is very likely, which is insufficient.

In which of the following three scenarios does the defendant owe a duty to act?

Tyrion shoots an air-rifle at Circe. Circe is killed because of her weak heart. A healthy person would not have died. Is Tyrion a legal cause of Circe's death?

Incorrect . The defendant must take the victim as they find them, even if it is not foreseeable. This means that if the claimant has a special condition that makes them more likely to suffer harm (or more serious harm) than a normal person, the defendant is still taken to cause the harm: R v Hayward.

In which two scenarios will an act of the victim in bringing about a proscribed consequence break the chain of causation between the defendant's acts or omissions and the consequence?

Olaf shoots at Elsa with a rifle, intending to kill her. He misses and breaks an ice sculpture. Can Olaf's mens rea against Elsa be used to complete the offence of criminal damage?

Incorrect . Transferred malice only applies where the defendant has the mens rea for the same crime as the actus reus : R v Pembliton. The mens rea for murder and criminal damage are not the same.

Tyrion shoots an air-rifle at Circe. Circe is shot in the stomach. She is told by paramedics that she can be saved by a blood transfusion, but she refuses to consent because she is a Jehovah's Witness. She dies. Is Tyrion a legal cause of Circe's death?

Incorrect . The defendant must take the victim as they find them, even if it is not foreseeable. This means that if the claimant has a particular world-view or belief system which leads them to reject treatment, causation is unbroken: R v Holland .

Dee is charged with an offence with a mens rea of negligence. Which of her special characteristics can be attributed to the reasonable person?

Incorrect . Negligence is an objective test. The defendant's special characteristics and particular beliefs do not matter unless they are reasonable: R v C . There is an exception where the defendant is a child - the reasonable person is taken to be the same age as the defendant: R (RSPCA) v C.

In which two scenarios will an act of a third-party in bringing about a proscribed consequence break the chain of causation between the defendant's acts or omissions and the consequence?

Most criminal offences can be committed by omission. True or false?

Incorrect . Most offences cannot be committed by omission unless there is a duty to act, while a minority can be committed by omission even in the absence of a duty to act. Some offences, such as assault, can never be committed by omission.

Harold is randomly stopped in the street, holding a perfectly ordinary-looking, sealed package. He is asked whether there are drugs inside. Harold answers that he is not certain, because the package is not his and he found it at a bus-stop. However, Harold also says that he thinks it is likely that the package contains drugs because the wood elves in his garden told him so, and they don't often lie. The package is full of cocaine. The police want to charge him with an offence which stipulates that the defendant has reasonable grounds to suspect they possess drugs. Does Harold meet this criteria?

Incorrect . 'Reasonable grounds to believe/know/suspect' is a form of mens rea in which the defendant must usually both subjectively suspect/know/believe the relevant thing, and his suspicion must be objectively reasonable: R v Saik. Harold's grounds for suspicion are not reasonable and there are no reasons stated which would lead a reasonable person to suspect that the package contains drugs.

When is a defendant reckless as to a consequence happening or a circumstance existing?

Incorrect . Recklessness is defined as foresight that the proscribed result might come about if the defendant acts as he does or that a particular state of affairs exists. There is no need for the risk to be significant, but it must also be unreasonable for the defendant to take the risk: R v G. Unless the offence states otherwise, recklessness is a subjective standard.

Murder is a crime of specific intent. True or false?

Incorrect . See R v O'Connor .

Alfred is a doctor treating Zin, a comatose patient. He turns off her life support machine, and she dies due an inability to breathe unassisted. Has Alfred killed Zin by an act or an omission?

Incorrect . In medical cases, the courts usually view the cessation of treatment as an omission even when it involves positive acts (such as unplugging a life support machine): Airedale National Health Service Trust v Bland.

Harold is arrested when he is found in possession of a strange package. He is asked whether there are drugs inside, and he answers 'yes'. The package turns out to be full of coriander, because Harold's roommate Claude stole all the drugs and replaced them with herbs before the arrest. Was Harold's state of mind one of knowledge or belief?

Incorrect . Knowledge is true belief, and Harold was incorrect about the contents of the package. He therefore did not know there were drugs inside.

A defendant is very intoxicated on alcohol when he commits an offence. Does this negate the mens rea for the offence?

Incorrect . The fact that the defendant was intoxicated when they committed the crime does not, in itself, negate mens rea : DPP v Beard.

Lacy burns down a house for insurance money, knowing that Eric is inside, tied to a bed and unable to escape. She claims she did not want Eric dead, but she knew he would certainly die and did not care enough to untie him first. Did Lacey intend to kill Eric?

Incorrect . Since Lacey knew it was virtually certain Eric would die, she has oblique intent to kill him: R v Woollin.

Section 18 of the Offences Against the Person Act 1861 is a crime of basic intent. True or false?

Incorrect . See R v Brown and Stratton .

In which two scenarios is the defendant's intoxication relevant to his guilt for an offence?

Section 20 of the Offences Against the Person Act 1861 is a crime of specific intent. True or false?

Incorrect . See DPP v Majewski.

Your score is

Share this:

criminal law essay on causation

  • Search Menu

Sign in through your institution

  • Browse content in Arts and Humanities
  • Browse content in Archaeology
  • Anglo-Saxon and Medieval Archaeology
  • Archaeological Methodology and Techniques
  • Archaeology by Region
  • Archaeology of Religion
  • Archaeology of Trade and Exchange
  • Biblical Archaeology
  • Contemporary and Public Archaeology
  • Environmental Archaeology
  • Historical Archaeology
  • History and Theory of Archaeology
  • Industrial Archaeology
  • Landscape Archaeology
  • Mortuary Archaeology
  • Prehistoric Archaeology
  • Underwater Archaeology
  • Zooarchaeology
  • Browse content in Architecture
  • Architectural Structure and Design
  • History of Architecture
  • Residential and Domestic Buildings
  • Theory of Architecture
  • Browse content in Art
  • Art Subjects and Themes
  • History of Art
  • Industrial and Commercial Art
  • Theory of Art
  • Biographical Studies
  • Byzantine Studies
  • Browse content in Classical Studies
  • Classical Numismatics
  • Classical Literature
  • Classical Reception
  • Classical History
  • Classical Philosophy
  • Classical Mythology
  • Classical Art and Architecture
  • Classical Oratory and Rhetoric
  • Greek and Roman Archaeology
  • Greek and Roman Papyrology
  • Greek and Roman Epigraphy
  • Greek and Roman Law
  • Late Antiquity
  • Religion in the Ancient World
  • Social History
  • Digital Humanities
  • Browse content in History
  • Colonialism and Imperialism
  • Diplomatic History
  • Environmental History
  • Genealogy, Heraldry, Names, and Honours
  • Genocide and Ethnic Cleansing
  • Historical Geography
  • History by Period
  • History of Agriculture
  • History of Education
  • History of Emotions
  • History of Gender and Sexuality
  • Industrial History
  • Intellectual History
  • International History
  • Labour History
  • Legal and Constitutional History
  • Local and Family History
  • Maritime History
  • Military History
  • National Liberation and Post-Colonialism
  • Oral History
  • Political History
  • Public History
  • Regional and National History
  • Revolutions and Rebellions
  • Slavery and Abolition of Slavery
  • Social and Cultural History
  • Theory, Methods, and Historiography
  • Urban History
  • World History
  • Browse content in Language Teaching and Learning
  • Language Learning (Specific Skills)
  • Language Teaching Theory and Methods
  • Browse content in Linguistics
  • Applied Linguistics
  • Cognitive Linguistics
  • Computational Linguistics
  • Forensic Linguistics
  • Grammar, Syntax and Morphology
  • Historical and Diachronic Linguistics
  • History of English
  • Language Variation
  • Language Families
  • Language Evolution
  • Language Reference
  • Language Acquisition
  • Lexicography
  • Linguistic Theories
  • Linguistic Typology
  • Linguistic Anthropology
  • Phonetics and Phonology
  • Psycholinguistics
  • Sociolinguistics
  • Translation and Interpretation
  • Writing Systems
  • Browse content in Literature
  • Bibliography
  • Children's Literature Studies
  • Literary Studies (Modernism)
  • Literary Studies (Romanticism)
  • Literary Studies (American)
  • Literary Studies (Asian)
  • Literary Studies (European)
  • Literary Studies (Eco-criticism)
  • Literary Studies - World
  • Literary Studies (1500 to 1800)
  • Literary Studies (19th Century)
  • Literary Studies (20th Century onwards)
  • Literary Studies (African American Literature)
  • Literary Studies (British and Irish)
  • Literary Studies (Early and Medieval)
  • Literary Studies (Fiction, Novelists, and Prose Writers)
  • Literary Studies (Gender Studies)
  • Literary Studies (Graphic Novels)
  • Literary Studies (History of the Book)
  • Literary Studies (Plays and Playwrights)
  • Literary Studies (Poetry and Poets)
  • Literary Studies (Postcolonial Literature)
  • Literary Studies (Queer Studies)
  • Literary Studies (Science Fiction)
  • Literary Studies (Travel Literature)
  • Literary Studies (War Literature)
  • Literary Studies (Women's Writing)
  • Literary Theory and Cultural Studies
  • Mythology and Folklore
  • Shakespeare Studies and Criticism
  • Browse content in Media Studies
  • Browse content in Music
  • Applied Music
  • Dance and Music
  • Ethics in Music
  • Ethnomusicology
  • Gender and Sexuality in Music
  • Medicine and Music
  • Music Cultures
  • Music and Culture
  • Music and Media
  • Music and Religion
  • Music Education and Pedagogy
  • Music Theory and Analysis
  • Musical Scores, Lyrics, and Libretti
  • Musical Structures, Styles, and Techniques
  • Musicology and Music History
  • Performance Practice and Studies
  • Race and Ethnicity in Music
  • Sound Studies
  • Browse content in Performing Arts
  • Browse content in Philosophy
  • Aesthetics and Philosophy of Art
  • Epistemology
  • Feminist Philosophy
  • History of Western Philosophy
  • Metaphysics
  • Moral Philosophy
  • Non-Western Philosophy
  • Philosophy of Action
  • Philosophy of Law
  • Philosophy of Religion
  • Philosophy of Language
  • Philosophy of Mind
  • Philosophy of Perception
  • Philosophy of Science
  • Philosophy of Mathematics and Logic
  • Practical Ethics
  • Social and Political Philosophy
  • Browse content in Religion
  • Biblical Studies
  • Christianity
  • East Asian Religions
  • History of Religion
  • Judaism and Jewish Studies
  • Qumran Studies
  • Religion and Education
  • Religion and Health
  • Religion and Politics
  • Religion and Science
  • Religion and Law
  • Religion and Art, Literature, and Music
  • Religious Studies
  • Browse content in Society and Culture
  • Cookery, Food, and Drink
  • Cultural Studies
  • Customs and Traditions
  • Ethical Issues and Debates
  • Hobbies, Games, Arts and Crafts
  • Natural world, Country Life, and Pets
  • Popular Beliefs and Controversial Knowledge
  • Sports and Outdoor Recreation
  • Technology and Society
  • Travel and Holiday
  • Visual Culture
  • Browse content in Law
  • Arbitration
  • Browse content in Company and Commercial Law
  • Commercial Law
  • Company Law
  • Browse content in Comparative Law
  • Systems of Law
  • Competition Law
  • Browse content in Constitutional and Administrative Law
  • Government Powers
  • Judicial Review
  • Local Government Law
  • Military and Defence Law
  • Parliamentary and Legislative Practice
  • Construction Law
  • Contract Law
  • Browse content in Criminal Law
  • Criminal Procedure
  • Criminal Evidence Law
  • Sentencing and Punishment
  • Employment and Labour Law
  • Environment and Energy Law
  • Browse content in Financial Law
  • Banking Law
  • Insolvency Law
  • History of Law
  • Human Rights and Immigration
  • Intellectual Property Law
  • Browse content in International Law
  • Private International Law and Conflict of Laws
  • Public International Law
  • IT and Communications Law
  • Jurisprudence and Philosophy of Law
  • Law and Society
  • Law and Politics
  • Browse content in Legal System and Practice
  • Courts and Procedure
  • Legal Skills and Practice
  • Legal System - Costs and Funding
  • Primary Sources of Law
  • Regulation of Legal Profession
  • Medical and Healthcare Law
  • Browse content in Policing
  • Criminal Investigation and Detection
  • Police and Security Services
  • Police Procedure and Law
  • Police Regional Planning
  • Browse content in Property Law
  • Personal Property Law
  • Restitution
  • Study and Revision
  • Terrorism and National Security Law
  • Browse content in Trusts Law
  • Wills and Probate or Succession
  • Browse content in Medicine and Health
  • Browse content in Allied Health Professions
  • Arts Therapies
  • Clinical Science
  • Dietetics and Nutrition
  • Occupational Therapy
  • Operating Department Practice
  • Physiotherapy
  • Radiography
  • Speech and Language Therapy
  • Browse content in Anaesthetics
  • General Anaesthesia
  • Clinical Neuroscience
  • Browse content in Clinical Medicine
  • Acute Medicine
  • Cardiovascular Medicine
  • Clinical Genetics
  • Clinical Pharmacology and Therapeutics
  • Dermatology
  • Endocrinology and Diabetes
  • Gastroenterology
  • Genito-urinary Medicine
  • Geriatric Medicine
  • Infectious Diseases
  • Medical Oncology
  • Medical Toxicology
  • Pain Medicine
  • Palliative Medicine
  • Rehabilitation Medicine
  • Respiratory Medicine and Pulmonology
  • Rheumatology
  • Sleep Medicine
  • Sports and Exercise Medicine
  • Community Medical Services
  • Critical Care
  • Emergency Medicine
  • Forensic Medicine
  • Haematology
  • History of Medicine
  • Medical Ethics
  • Browse content in Medical Skills
  • Clinical Skills
  • Communication Skills
  • Nursing Skills
  • Surgical Skills
  • Browse content in Medical Dentistry
  • Oral and Maxillofacial Surgery
  • Paediatric Dentistry
  • Restorative Dentistry and Orthodontics
  • Surgical Dentistry
  • Medical Statistics and Methodology
  • Browse content in Neurology
  • Clinical Neurophysiology
  • Neuropathology
  • Nursing Studies
  • Browse content in Obstetrics and Gynaecology
  • Gynaecology
  • Occupational Medicine
  • Ophthalmology
  • Otolaryngology (ENT)
  • Browse content in Paediatrics
  • Neonatology
  • Browse content in Pathology
  • Chemical Pathology
  • Clinical Cytogenetics and Molecular Genetics
  • Histopathology
  • Medical Microbiology and Virology
  • Patient Education and Information
  • Browse content in Pharmacology
  • Psychopharmacology
  • Browse content in Popular Health
  • Caring for Others
  • Complementary and Alternative Medicine
  • Self-help and Personal Development
  • Browse content in Preclinical Medicine
  • Cell Biology
  • Molecular Biology and Genetics
  • Reproduction, Growth and Development
  • Primary Care
  • Professional Development in Medicine
  • Browse content in Psychiatry
  • Addiction Medicine
  • Child and Adolescent Psychiatry
  • Forensic Psychiatry
  • Learning Disabilities
  • Old Age Psychiatry
  • Psychotherapy
  • Browse content in Public Health and Epidemiology
  • Epidemiology
  • Public Health
  • Browse content in Radiology
  • Clinical Radiology
  • Interventional Radiology
  • Nuclear Medicine
  • Radiation Oncology
  • Reproductive Medicine
  • Browse content in Surgery
  • Cardiothoracic Surgery
  • Gastro-intestinal and Colorectal Surgery
  • General Surgery
  • Neurosurgery
  • Paediatric Surgery
  • Peri-operative Care
  • Plastic and Reconstructive Surgery
  • Surgical Oncology
  • Transplant Surgery
  • Trauma and Orthopaedic Surgery
  • Vascular Surgery
  • Browse content in Science and Mathematics
  • Browse content in Biological Sciences
  • Aquatic Biology
  • Biochemistry
  • Bioinformatics and Computational Biology
  • Developmental Biology
  • Ecology and Conservation
  • Evolutionary Biology
  • Genetics and Genomics
  • Microbiology
  • Molecular and Cell Biology
  • Natural History
  • Plant Sciences and Forestry
  • Research Methods in Life Sciences
  • Structural Biology
  • Systems Biology
  • Zoology and Animal Sciences
  • Browse content in Chemistry
  • Analytical Chemistry
  • Computational Chemistry
  • Crystallography
  • Environmental Chemistry
  • Industrial Chemistry
  • Inorganic Chemistry
  • Materials Chemistry
  • Medicinal Chemistry
  • Mineralogy and Gems
  • Organic Chemistry
  • Physical Chemistry
  • Polymer Chemistry
  • Study and Communication Skills in Chemistry
  • Theoretical Chemistry
  • Browse content in Computer Science
  • Artificial Intelligence
  • Computer Architecture and Logic Design
  • Game Studies
  • Human-Computer Interaction
  • Mathematical Theory of Computation
  • Programming Languages
  • Software Engineering
  • Systems Analysis and Design
  • Virtual Reality
  • Browse content in Computing
  • Business Applications
  • Computer Games
  • Computer Security
  • Computer Networking and Communications
  • Digital Lifestyle
  • Graphical and Digital Media Applications
  • Operating Systems
  • Browse content in Earth Sciences and Geography
  • Atmospheric Sciences
  • Environmental Geography
  • Geology and the Lithosphere
  • Maps and Map-making
  • Meteorology and Climatology
  • Oceanography and Hydrology
  • Palaeontology
  • Physical Geography and Topography
  • Regional Geography
  • Soil Science
  • Urban Geography
  • Browse content in Engineering and Technology
  • Agriculture and Farming
  • Biological Engineering
  • Civil Engineering, Surveying, and Building
  • Electronics and Communications Engineering
  • Energy Technology
  • Engineering (General)
  • Environmental Science, Engineering, and Technology
  • History of Engineering and Technology
  • Mechanical Engineering and Materials
  • Technology of Industrial Chemistry
  • Transport Technology and Trades
  • Browse content in Environmental Science
  • Applied Ecology (Environmental Science)
  • Conservation of the Environment (Environmental Science)
  • Environmental Sustainability
  • Environmentalist Thought and Ideology (Environmental Science)
  • Management of Land and Natural Resources (Environmental Science)
  • Natural Disasters (Environmental Science)
  • Nuclear Issues (Environmental Science)
  • Pollution and Threats to the Environment (Environmental Science)
  • Social Impact of Environmental Issues (Environmental Science)
  • History of Science and Technology
  • Browse content in Materials Science
  • Ceramics and Glasses
  • Composite Materials
  • Metals, Alloying, and Corrosion
  • Nanotechnology
  • Browse content in Mathematics
  • Applied Mathematics
  • Biomathematics and Statistics
  • History of Mathematics
  • Mathematical Education
  • Mathematical Finance
  • Mathematical Analysis
  • Numerical and Computational Mathematics
  • Probability and Statistics
  • Pure Mathematics
  • Browse content in Neuroscience
  • Cognition and Behavioural Neuroscience
  • Development of the Nervous System
  • Disorders of the Nervous System
  • History of Neuroscience
  • Invertebrate Neurobiology
  • Molecular and Cellular Systems
  • Neuroendocrinology and Autonomic Nervous System
  • Neuroscientific Techniques
  • Sensory and Motor Systems
  • Browse content in Physics
  • Astronomy and Astrophysics
  • Atomic, Molecular, and Optical Physics
  • Biological and Medical Physics
  • Classical Mechanics
  • Computational Physics
  • Condensed Matter Physics
  • Electromagnetism, Optics, and Acoustics
  • History of Physics
  • Mathematical and Statistical Physics
  • Measurement Science
  • Nuclear Physics
  • Particles and Fields
  • Plasma Physics
  • Quantum Physics
  • Relativity and Gravitation
  • Semiconductor and Mesoscopic Physics
  • Browse content in Psychology
  • Affective Sciences
  • Clinical Psychology
  • Cognitive Neuroscience
  • Cognitive Psychology
  • Criminal and Forensic Psychology
  • Developmental Psychology
  • Educational Psychology
  • Evolutionary Psychology
  • Health Psychology
  • History and Systems in Psychology
  • Music Psychology
  • Neuropsychology
  • Organizational Psychology
  • Psychological Assessment and Testing
  • Psychology of Human-Technology Interaction
  • Psychology Professional Development and Training
  • Research Methods in Psychology
  • Social Psychology
  • Browse content in Social Sciences
  • Browse content in Anthropology
  • Anthropology of Religion
  • Human Evolution
  • Medical Anthropology
  • Physical Anthropology
  • Regional Anthropology
  • Social and Cultural Anthropology
  • Theory and Practice of Anthropology
  • Browse content in Business and Management
  • Business History
  • Business Ethics
  • Business Strategy
  • Business and Technology
  • Business and Government
  • Business and the Environment
  • Comparative Management
  • Corporate Governance
  • Corporate Social Responsibility
  • Entrepreneurship
  • Health Management
  • Human Resource Management
  • Industrial and Employment Relations
  • Industry Studies
  • Information and Communication Technologies
  • International Business
  • Knowledge Management
  • Management and Management Techniques
  • Operations Management
  • Organizational Theory and Behaviour
  • Pensions and Pension Management
  • Public and Nonprofit Management
  • Social Issues in Business and Management
  • Strategic Management
  • Supply Chain Management
  • Browse content in Criminology and Criminal Justice
  • Criminal Justice
  • Criminology
  • Forms of Crime
  • International and Comparative Criminology
  • Youth Violence and Juvenile Justice
  • Development Studies
  • Browse content in Economics
  • Agricultural, Environmental, and Natural Resource Economics
  • Asian Economics
  • Behavioural Finance
  • Behavioural Economics and Neuroeconomics
  • Econometrics and Mathematical Economics
  • Economic Methodology
  • Economic History
  • Economic Systems
  • Economic Development and Growth
  • Financial Markets
  • Financial Institutions and Services
  • General Economics and Teaching
  • Health, Education, and Welfare
  • History of Economic Thought
  • International Economics
  • Labour and Demographic Economics
  • Law and Economics
  • Macroeconomics and Monetary Economics
  • Microeconomics
  • Public Economics
  • Urban, Rural, and Regional Economics
  • Welfare Economics
  • Browse content in Education
  • Adult Education and Continuous Learning
  • Care and Counselling of Students
  • Early Childhood and Elementary Education
  • Educational Equipment and Technology
  • Educational Strategies and Policy
  • Higher and Further Education
  • Organization and Management of Education
  • Philosophy and Theory of Education
  • Schools Studies
  • Secondary Education
  • Teaching of a Specific Subject
  • Teaching of Specific Groups and Special Educational Needs
  • Teaching Skills and Techniques
  • Browse content in Environment
  • Applied Ecology (Social Science)
  • Climate Change
  • Conservation of the Environment (Social Science)
  • Environmentalist Thought and Ideology (Social Science)
  • Management of Land and Natural Resources (Social Science)
  • Natural Disasters (Environment)
  • Pollution and Threats to the Environment (Social Science)
  • Social Impact of Environmental Issues (Social Science)
  • Sustainability
  • Browse content in Human Geography
  • Cultural Geography
  • Economic Geography
  • Political Geography
  • Browse content in Interdisciplinary Studies
  • Communication Studies
  • Museums, Libraries, and Information Sciences
  • Browse content in Politics
  • African Politics
  • Asian Politics
  • Chinese Politics
  • Comparative Politics
  • Conflict Politics
  • Elections and Electoral Studies
  • Environmental Politics
  • Ethnic Politics
  • European Union
  • Foreign Policy
  • Gender and Politics
  • Human Rights and Politics
  • Indian Politics
  • International Relations
  • International Organization (Politics)
  • Irish Politics
  • Latin American Politics
  • Middle Eastern Politics
  • Political Theory
  • Political Behaviour
  • Political Economy
  • Political Institutions
  • Political Methodology
  • Political Communication
  • Political Philosophy
  • Political Sociology
  • Politics and Law
  • Politics of Development
  • Public Policy
  • Public Administration
  • Qualitative Political Methodology
  • Quantitative Political Methodology
  • Regional Political Studies
  • Russian Politics
  • Security Studies
  • State and Local Government
  • UK Politics
  • US Politics
  • Browse content in Regional and Area Studies
  • African Studies
  • Asian Studies
  • East Asian Studies
  • Japanese Studies
  • Latin American Studies
  • Middle Eastern Studies
  • Native American Studies
  • Scottish Studies
  • Browse content in Research and Information
  • Research Methods
  • Browse content in Social Work
  • Addictions and Substance Misuse
  • Adoption and Fostering
  • Care of the Elderly
  • Child and Adolescent Social Work
  • Couple and Family Social Work
  • Direct Practice and Clinical Social Work
  • Emergency Services
  • Human Behaviour and the Social Environment
  • International and Global Issues in Social Work
  • Mental and Behavioural Health
  • Social Justice and Human Rights
  • Social Policy and Advocacy
  • Social Work and Crime and Justice
  • Social Work Macro Practice
  • Social Work Practice Settings
  • Social Work Research and Evidence-based Practice
  • Welfare and Benefit Systems
  • Browse content in Sociology
  • Childhood Studies
  • Community Development
  • Comparative and Historical Sociology
  • Disability Studies
  • Economic Sociology
  • Gender and Sexuality
  • Gerontology and Ageing
  • Health, Illness, and Medicine
  • Marriage and the Family
  • Migration Studies
  • Occupations, Professions, and Work
  • Organizations
  • Population and Demography
  • Race and Ethnicity
  • Social Theory
  • Social Movements and Social Change
  • Social Research and Statistics
  • Social Stratification, Inequality, and Mobility
  • Sociology of Religion
  • Sociology of Education
  • Sport and Leisure
  • Urban and Rural Studies
  • Browse content in Warfare and Defence
  • Defence Strategy, Planning, and Research
  • Land Forces and Warfare
  • Military Administration
  • Military Life and Institutions
  • Naval Forces and Warfare
  • Other Warfare and Defence Issues
  • Peace Studies and Conflict Resolution
  • Weapons and Equipment

Criminal Responsibility

  • < Previous chapter
  • Next chapter >

6 The Nature of Causation

  • Published: March 2007
  • Cite Icon Cite
  • Permissions Icon Permissions

This chapter is concerned with the best way to understand causation in the criminal law. It is argued that there is a close parallel, with respect to central doctrines of causation, between causation in law and morality on the one hand and causation in science on the other. However, in law and morality we cannot separate the question from causation neatly from the question of whether the defendant had mens rea for his conduct.

Personal account

  • Sign in with email/username & password
  • Get email alerts
  • Save searches
  • Purchase content
  • Activate your purchase/trial code
  • Add your ORCID iD

Institutional access

Sign in with a library card.

  • Sign in with username/password
  • Recommend to your librarian
  • Institutional account management
  • Get help with access

Access to content on Oxford Academic is often provided through institutional subscriptions and purchases. If you are a member of an institution with an active account, you may be able to access content in one of the following ways:

IP based access

Typically, access is provided across an institutional network to a range of IP addresses. This authentication occurs automatically, and it is not possible to sign out of an IP authenticated account.

Choose this option to get remote access when outside your institution. Shibboleth/Open Athens technology is used to provide single sign-on between your institution’s website and Oxford Academic.

  • Click Sign in through your institution.
  • Select your institution from the list provided, which will take you to your institution's website to sign in.
  • When on the institution site, please use the credentials provided by your institution. Do not use an Oxford Academic personal account.
  • Following successful sign in, you will be returned to Oxford Academic.

If your institution is not listed or you cannot sign in to your institution’s website, please contact your librarian or administrator.

Enter your library card number to sign in. If you cannot sign in, please contact your librarian.

Society Members

Society member access to a journal is achieved in one of the following ways:

Sign in through society site

Many societies offer single sign-on between the society website and Oxford Academic. If you see ‘Sign in through society site’ in the sign in pane within a journal:

  • Click Sign in through society site.
  • When on the society site, please use the credentials provided by that society. Do not use an Oxford Academic personal account.

If you do not have a society account or have forgotten your username or password, please contact your society.

Sign in using a personal account

Some societies use Oxford Academic personal accounts to provide access to their members. See below.

A personal account can be used to get email alerts, save searches, purchase content, and activate subscriptions.

Some societies use Oxford Academic personal accounts to provide access to their members.

Viewing your signed in accounts

Click the account icon in the top right to:

  • View your signed in personal account and access account management features.
  • View the institutional accounts that are providing access.

Signed in but can't access content

Oxford Academic is home to a wide variety of products. The institutional subscription may not cover the content that you are trying to access. If you believe you should have access to that content, please contact your librarian.

For librarians and administrators, your personal account also provides access to institutional account management. Here you will find options to view and activate subscriptions, manage institutional settings and access options, access usage statistics, and more.

Our books are available by subscription or purchase to libraries and institutions.

Month: Total Views:
October 2022 10
November 2022 1
December 2022 11
January 2023 16
February 2023 1
March 2023 4
April 2023 13
May 2023 21
June 2023 6
July 2023 3
August 2023 3
September 2023 9
October 2023 7
November 2023 15
December 2023 9
January 2024 4
February 2024 7
March 2024 15
April 2024 13
May 2024 4
June 2024 5
July 2024 6
  • About Oxford Academic
  • Publish journals with us
  • University press partners
  • What we publish
  • New features  
  • Open access
  • Rights and permissions
  • Accessibility
  • Advertising
  • Media enquiries
  • Oxford University Press
  • Oxford Languages
  • University of Oxford

Oxford University Press is a department of the University of Oxford. It furthers the University's objective of excellence in research, scholarship, and education by publishing worldwide

  • Copyright © 2024 Oxford University Press
  • Cookie settings
  • Cookie policy
  • Privacy policy
  • Legal notice

This Feature Is Available To Subscribers Only

Sign In or Create an Account

This PDF is available to Subscribers Only

For full access to this pdf, sign in to an existing account, or purchase an annual subscription.

King's College London Logo

Causation in (Criminal) Law

Research output : Contribution to journal › Article › peer-review

Original languageEnglish
Pages (from-to)416-441
Number of pages26
Journal
Volume133
Issue number3
Early online date31 Jul 2017
Publication statusPublished - Jul 2017
  • Criminal law
  • Responsibility

This output contributes to the following UN Sustainable Development Goals (SDGs)

Access to Document

  • Causation in (Criminal) Law_SIMESTER_Accepted7April2016_GREEN AAM Accepted author manuscript, 316 KB
  • https://uk.practicallaw.thomsonreuters.com/Document/IE4D5E0E051B211E7BAE893420045121E/View/FullText.html?originationContext=document&transitionType=DocumentItem&contextData=%28sc.Default%29&comp=wluk

Fingerprint

  • Elements Engineering 100%
  • Highlight Engineering 100%
  • Intersects Engineering 100%
  • Analysis Social Sciences 100%
  • Criminal Law Social Sciences 100%
  • Causation Arts and Humanities 100%
  • Process Social Sciences 50%
  • Element Medicine and Dentistry 50%

T1 - Causation in (Criminal) Law

AU - Simester, Andrew

PY - 2017/7

Y1 - 2017/7

N2 - Analyses the elements of causation in criminal law, with reference to the real-world processes involved. Discusses direct causation arising from physical chain reactions of consecutive events, including the operating cause requirement, and highlights how the analysis differs from that used in R. v Hughes (Michael) (SC). Details aspects of indirect causation in which multiple chains of direct causation intersect, and causation due to omissions.

AB - Analyses the elements of causation in criminal law, with reference to the real-world processes involved. Discusses direct causation arising from physical chain reactions of consecutive events, including the operating cause requirement, and highlights how the analysis differs from that used in R. v Hughes (Michael) (SC). Details aspects of indirect causation in which multiple chains of direct causation intersect, and causation due to omissions.

KW - Criminal law

KW - CAUSATION

KW - Responsibility

M3 - Article

SN - 0023-933X

JO - Law Quarterly Review

JF - Law Quarterly Review

Free law study resources

No notifications.

Disclaimer: This essay has been written by a law student and not by our expert law writers. View examples of our professional work here .

View full disclaimer

Any opinions, findings, conclusions, or recommendations expressed in this material are those of the authors and do not reflect the views of LawTeacher.net. You should not treat any information in this essay as being authoritative.

Causation Is Only Important in Situation Where a Crime Has Been Committed

Info: 3745 words (15 pages) Essay Published: 29th May 2019

Reference this

Causation can be established through either factual or legal causation. The method for establishing a factual causation is the ‘But For’ test. This test simply means that if not for the defendants account, would any harm have occurred? If the answer is ‘No’, then we can say the defendant caused the death of his victim. This test is very important and it’s a test of necessity. In circumstances where there are no complicating factors, factual causation will be sufficient to establish causation but where there are complicating factors, legal causation will be needed to establish causation.

When establishing legal causation, the following principles have to be considered;

It must be visible that the defendant’s action is the substantial cause. It need not be the sole cause of the harm but it must be significant. The defendant’s behavior must contribute and be a significant cause of its result and it must not be more than insignificant to the result or de minimis as seen in Cato 1976.

In the case of Kennedy No2 (2007), it was held that the defendants contribution need only be significant, it need not be substantial.

In a situation where A stabbed B about three times and B died, it would have to be established whether A actually stabbed B and if he did with the necessary mens rea. In this example, A causing B’s death is self evident and significant to the result.

But there are instances whereby problems may arise if A says the death was not caused by his act of stabbing B, but by the act of the doctor who treated B negligently at the hospital, it can still be said that A’s action is still a significant cause of B’s death. In this situation, the court will have to decided where the doctors action has broken the chain of causation so as to relieve the defendant of the for the killing. Whatever the court decides, D would still be liable for causing serious injury to B.

The harm caused or inflicted upon the victim must result from a culpable act. i.e. the act must be capable in law as amounting to the death of the victim and it must be an act where the defendant would be responsible for his actions. In Dalloway, a driver of a spring cart, standing in the cart and driving along a public road without reins, but not driving furiously, when a child runs across the road before the cart, and is killed by the wheel passing over it, is not guilty of manslaughter, unless he could have saved the life of the child if he had been driving with reins in his hand.

You must take your victim as you find them. This is also known as the thin skull rule. This rule applies irrespective of whether the defendant was aware of the condition or not. If you hit your victim, no matter whether your intention was to cause slight harm, if it results into a very serious injury which leads to death, then you will be liable for manslaughter under what is known as unlawful act doctrine and this means that he deliberately committed the unlawful and dangerous act. This means if he has a particularly vulnerable victim he is fully liable for the consequences to them even if an ordinary person would not have suffered such severe consequences. For example if D commits a minor assault on V who has a heart condition and V suffers a heart attack and dies. D is liable for the death of V even though such an attack would result in no physical harm to someone without a heart condition.

In Blaue (1975), Lawton L. J held that “it does not lie in the mouth of the assailant to say that the victim’s religious beliefs which prevented him from accepting certain types of treatment were unreasonable. So the refusal of your victim to treatment would not relieve you of liability in the thin skull rule. And so it wouldn’t break the chain of causation.

There are also situations whereby the defendant claims that the chain of causation which connects his conduct with the result has been broken by an intervening event and this intervening event is usually refered to as a ‘novus actus interveniens which simply means a ‘new act’.

Semester and sullivian explained in their book that a “novus actus is an action or an event which ‘intervenes’ to ‘break the causal chain’ leading from D to the eventual harm” Where the result is attributable to a novus actus, D is relieved of the liability for that results and his conduct is no longer seen as a significant and operating cause.

Different tests apply to decide if the chain of causation has been broken depending on the type of intervening act. But I would like to group these intervening acts into four which are as follows;

Natural causes- this can be explained as events which occur by act of God. It involves natural events other than human beings acts.

Again, principles of foreseeability determine whether a naturally-occurring event will amount to an intervening act which breaks the chain of causation. For example, in Hart (1986), D assaulted V, leaving her lying conscious on a beach below the high-water mark. V was subsequently drowned by the incoming tide. The court of appeal held that D had caused the death of the victim. A freak wave is an unpredictable event so it is likely to be unforeseeable and would have amounted to an intervening act in the case of Hart if V was left lying above high water mark. But in a situation in which an unconscious victim is left below the tide line and drowns when the tide comes in. This is a wholly foreseeable occurrence so it will not break the chain of causation. Even though the defendant did not drown the victim directly, he put the victim in a position where it was foreseeable that the victim would drown so liability would be established.

Act of a third party- the issue of causation arises whereby there is a conduct by a third party. A person is normally responsible for whatever act he does himself but can’t be liable for the act of another all because his actions provided a background for a consequent event. If A beats up B and leaves him on the railway and a train passes and runs over B, A will be liable for the death of B because it will be said that A could have foreseen what was going to happen by leaving B on the railway. but where A leaves B by the road side and C comes and strangles B to death, then we can say C’s intervention has broken the chain of causation. The unforeseeable intervention of another breaks the chain of causation and also the free, deliberate and informed intervention of a third party will relieve D of responsibility. In Pagett, P held a girl he kidnapped in front of him as a shield and then shot at armed police officers who immediately fired back, killing the girl, he was charged with manslaughter but he argued that the police actions constituted a break in the chain of causation but the court said that the accused act need not be the sole cause of the victims death and so it was held that P was liable for the death of the girl.

Act of the victim –the chain of causation cannot be broken here unless the victim’s acts are disproportionate or unreasonable in the circumstance. But initially you have to take your victim as you find them as I explained earlier. In fright and flight cases, the test of reasonable foreseeability (Was the victim’s reaction within the range of reasonably foreseeable responses? (Reed A 2009)) is really important. The accused can be held liable for harm/injuries suffered by the victim in trying to avoid violence at the hands of the defendants if it was reasonably foreseen. In Roberts (1972), the defendant interfered with the victim’s clothing whilst she was a passenger in his car. She jumped from the moving vehicle and sustained serious injuries in the fall. The defendant denied causing these injuries but his conviction was upheld as it was foreseeable that the victim would attempt to escape and could be injured in doing so. The chain of causation will be broken only if the victim’s actions were ‘so daft’ as to be unforeseeable. Also in Williams (1992), Halliday (1889) and Mackie (1973), it was explained that what their victims did was reasonably foreseeable as the result of what the defendants did or said. But in situations where no reasonable man would have expected to foresee the result, then the chain of causation would be broken (Reed A, p.43). Where the defendant is still a significant and operating cause at the time of the victim’s death, then it is irrelevant that there are other causes too also operating and this was the view in Blaue(1975), Smith(1959) and Dear (1996).

Medical intervention; this arises in most cases where the defendant committed an offence which led his victim to the hospital, and while in the hospital, the victim receives poor treatment and dies and he’s charged with either murder or manslaughter. The defendant argues that the act of the doctor has broken the chain of causation. In this situation, the court will have to decide whether the doctor’s conduct has broken the chain of causation so as to relieve the defendant of liability for unlawful homicide. Whatever the court decides, if the act of the doctor has broken the chain of causation, the defendant will still be liable for the serious injury he inflicted upon the victim. Where medical intervention contributes to death, the courts have been inconsistent in their approach and this is because in some situations, the defendant still remains liable no matter what happens while in some other cases, the hospital or doctor relieves the defendant of the liability. Reed A, Fitzpatrick B 2009, p.53 in their book explained that causation is a matter of law for the judge and where the wound inflicted by the accused is still an operating cause, the accused will remain liable even though the doctor were grossly negligent as in the cases of Smith and Blaue. In Cheshire and Jordan it was explained that where the initial wound is longer life threatening, the accused may still be held liable for the death brought about by the poor treatment of the staff. In Malcherek and Steel 1981, it explains that where the doctors are of the view that all necessary tests have been done and the victim will never recover and thereafter switch off the life support system, the chain of causation cannot be broken and so the accused will be liable for the death of his victim

The intervening acts or events which lead to break in causation are still governing the existing law on causation principles. There is a widely held view that the concept of causation is manipulated firstly in other to finding some persons who play a causal role and also foresee a consequence. It helps you find the person who committed a particular crime and allows the punishment he deserves.

Causation really plays an important role in criminal law in the sense that it satisfies the needs to punish someone who is felt to be deserving the punishment for his unacceptable behavior and an intervening act or break in chain of causation helps to reduce the punishment of the defendant to a minimal one for instance if D hits V on the head and he goes unconscious, if he dies, D would be liable of Manslaughter but if another party shots V and V dies, the act of the third party will relieve D of liability of manslaughter but D will still be liable for the injury he inflicted upon V.

The principle of foreseeability is in conflict with “take your victim as you find him” in the sense that whatever the result of what D did to V, the principle or test of reasonably foreseeability is involved because the law treats the pre-existing natural condition or vulnerability in the victim as foreseeable and the defendants must take the conditions of their victims as they find them.

In a situation whereby, the break in chain of causation occurs though the intervention of a natural cause, there would be nobody to be blamed or punished for the death of the victim and also where a person mistakenly commits an act that breaks the chain in causation, would the defendant be relieved of the liability or would he still be liable? These are questions which have not yet been looked into very well.

Under medical cases, in novus actus interveniens , the main problem here is that the juries have not be consistent in their approach and it is impossible to be precise and comprehensive about the principles governing the attribution of causation.

ORMEROD & FORTSON (2005) Under the issue of causation, for D to be liable as a principal for the offence of unlawful act manslaughter based on his conduct under s.23 of OAPA leading to V’s death, the prosecution are obliged to establish the causal element integral to the s.23 offence, and in addition, as an element of the offence of manslaughter that that unlawful act caused death. The orthodox view of causation is that the prosecution will fail to fulfill even the first of these. If D supplies the syringe and the heroin, and V self-injects, V has performed a free deliberate informed act of self-administration, and it is that act which represents the administration

Orthodoxy holds that in these circumstances V is regarded as administering to himself. In terms of general principles of causation, as Glanville Williams explained:

“The new intervening act (novus actus interveniens ) of a responsible actor, who had full knowledge of what he is doing, and is not subject to mistake or pressure, will normally operate to relieve the defendant of liability for a further consequence, because it makes the consequence too remote … What a person does (if he has reached adult years, is of sound mind and is not acting under mistake, intimidation or other similar pressure) is his own responsibility, and is not regarded as having been caused by other people.” This approach has been repeatedly adopted and approved by the appellate courts in a diverse range of circumstances like Pagett (1983), Latif (1996).However, in the context of drug administration cases; the courts have released their grip on this seemingly settled principle. In Kennedy No.1 it was suggested that D would still be responsible for the administration despite V’s act. Subsequently, in Dias, although the court endorsed the orthodox approach to causation, it did so with one significant reservation.

However, in the context of drug administration cases, the courts have released their grip on this seemingly settled principle. In Kennedy No.1 it was suggested that D would still be responsible for the administration despite V’s act. Subsequently, in Dias, although the court endorsed the orthodox approach to causation, it did so with one significant reservation.

In Kennedy No.2, the court is, unfortunately, less direct in its discussion of causation. The Lord Chief Justice states that;

“It has to be remembered that when considering whether the defendant’s act has caused death, what amounts to causation in a case of this nature is not dependent upon a particular statutory context. Accordingly if a defendant is acting in concert with the deceased, what the deceased does in concert with the defendant will not break the chain of causation, even though the general principles as to causation have to be applied. This was recognised by Lord Steyn when he qualified the general position when saying in R v Latif & Others [1996] 2 Cr. App. R. 92 at p 104: ‘The free, deliberate and informed intervention of a second person, who intends to exploit the situation created by the first, but is not acting in concert with him is held to relieve the first actor of criminal responsibility.’ (Emphasis added)”

In short, the court sidesteps causation by preferring a “joint responsibility” approach to liability.

Administration of drugs- In Evans, the court of appeal ruled on two important points

Whether or not a duty of care arises is a pure question of law

Whether Evans owed a duty in law to counteract the situation which she had created and so the appeal was dismissed.

Rogers was of the view that the only way to evade this conclusion is to say that the notion of “creating a dangerous situation” is somehow different and broader than the standard principles of causation.

Rogers was of the view that the decision was well decided because the drug supplier could have called for help after becoming aware of the clients illness. Evans provides for punishment if he does fails fails to call the ambulance and the client dies.

In Evans, the duty of care only arises ‘when they know or ought treasonably to know’ that the client has become seriously ill.

Here the burden of proof is on close friends, family members who supply the drugs.

In the kennedy and evans, if the principles of causation is about imputing moral blames, then it is defensible to say the drug dealer is guilty of the offence under s.23 of OAPA.

Every now and then, we do accept that the standing of the defendant and the victim may have some bearing on whether the victim’s act breaks the chain of causation.

Horder 2006. There has been a strong support for the approach to causation in which the destructive effect domestic abuse has on the victims autonomy can be regarded as rendering the defendant criminally liable for the victim suicide.

Under the principles of causation, an accessory to an offence should be regarded as liable to for the principal’s crime if the accessory caused the principal to commit that offence.

This not however a test of “but for” causation but simply whether the accessory can be considered to have materially contributed to the commission of the offence by the principal.

The reliance on the principle of causation is unfortunate for a number of reason;

Causation would be virtually impossible to prove in the context of joint enterprise liability e.g. where A and B intends to commit burglary and B along the line commits murder.

The modern law of causation would prevent any secondary liability from being established in many cases.

The principle of causation as identified by the court of appeal will create even more uncertainty for the jury, since it embodies a normative notion of whether the commission of the substantive offence should be attributed to the secondary party in some way. With no coherent suggestion as to when this would be appropriate

Causation is in some sense a difficult area of the law yet according to the court of appeal in Cato (1976) 1 WLR 110, Pagett (1983) 76 Cr App R 279 and Cheshire (1991) 1 WLR 844, the issue of factual causation is largerly one for the jury once the court has determined that there is sufficient evidence to be left to them and since ‘cause’ is an ordinary English word, in most cases no directions need to be given.

Allen was of the view that Lord Steyn’s dictum has been recognized as a statement of conventional doctrine. If a person is acting in concert there is a joint enterprise and those involved are either principals or accessories and the act of the principal in bringing about the prohibited result cannot amount to an intervening act negating the liability of another party who has aided and abetted the principal in performing the act

Williams was of the view that before the case of Finlay, the position in criminal law was simple. He explained that if the defendant caused the offensive result then he would be guilty as a principal.

Rogers, Finlay and Kennedy thus led to serious practical problems, widening the law until boundaries are no longer clear and weakening the line between accessory and principal liability. Williams said it’s not completely clear whether the new rules of causation are applicable outside the context of supply of drugs

In R v Mendez, the court of appeal identified a rationale for secondary liability namely the principle of causation such that an accessory should be regarded as liable for the principal’s crime if the accessory caused the principal to commit that offence.

Virgo said that the reliance on the principle of causation is unfortunate for a number of reasons. First, Causation would be virtually impossible to prove in the context of joint enterprise liability. Secondly, the modern law of causation would prevent any secondary liability from being established in many cases. Finally the principle of causation as identified by the courts of appeal will create even more uncertainty for the jury.

The principle of causation would not be able to relied on in the context of joint enterprise liability because causation would be virtually impossible to prove and it would prevent any secondary liability from being established.

In R v Dias[2001] subsequently a differently constituted court of appeal in the light of criticism of Kennedy No1 decision, adopted a different perspective, without actually overruling the earlier precedent. D’s conviction was quashed, despite the fact that he also admitted to having prepared a syringe and given it to the deceased. It was determined that the act of injecting oneself with a controlled drug is not a crime. Hence the defendant in Kennedy No1 could have been convicted as a secondary party by virtue of the fact that he had assisted and encouraged the deceased to inject himself.

The court of appeal in Dias asserted that in cases where D is accused of manslaughter because he supplied V with drugs, a conviction can only be upheld if the issue of causation is left to the jury to decide and this formed a mark of separation between Kennedy No1 and Dias; in Kennedy No1, the issue of causation had been left to the jury consideration, but in Dias, the court was mindful of the inconsistency effected by Kennedy No1 rationale and left it open to future days to decide that D caused V’s death even if V injected himself.

Dias and Rogers shared similar views in the sense that they both said that a person who supplies the drug or participated in the injection process would not be liable under sec 23 of OAPA 1861.

A further level of confusion arose in Kennedy No2 when the Criminal cases review commission had to refer the case of Kennedy No1 back to the court of appeal

Cite This Work

To export a reference to this article please select a referencing stye below:

Related Services

Student working on a laptop

  • Law Essay Writing Service

Student reading book

  • Law Dissertation Writing Service

Student reading and using laptop to study

  • Law Assignment Writing Service

DMCA / Removal Request

If you are the original writer of this essay and no longer wish to have your work published on LawTeacher.net then please:

Our academic writing and marking services can help you!

  • Marking Service
  • Samples of our Service
  • Full Service Portfolio

Study Resources

Free resources to assist you with your legal studies!

  • OSCOLA Referencing
  • SQE Study Guide
  • Legal Case Summaries
  • Act Summaries
  • Lecture Notes
  • Problem Question Examples
  • Law Study guides
  • UK Law Blog

Academic Knowledge Logo

Freelance Writing Jobs

Looking for a flexible role? Do you have a 2:1 degree or higher?

Academia.edu no longer supports Internet Explorer.

To browse Academia.edu and the wider internet faster and more securely, please take a few seconds to  upgrade your browser .

Enter the email address you signed up with and we'll email you a reset link.

  • We're Hiring!
  • Help Center

paper cover thumbnail

Causation in criminal law (Essay, BCL, 1st year)

Profile image of Yanis Oulmekki

Related Papers

Clare Tsimpourla

criminal law essay on causation

Loading Preview

Sorry, preview is currently unavailable. You can download the paper by clicking the button above.

RELATED TOPICS

  •   We're Hiring!
  •   Help Center
  • Find new research papers in:
  • Health Sciences
  • Earth Sciences
  • Cognitive Science
  • Mathematics
  • Computer Science
  • Academia ©2024

IMAGES

  1. (DOC) Causation in criminal law (Essay, BCL, 1st year)

    criminal law essay on causation

  2. Criminal Law Causation NCI Part 2

    criminal law essay on causation

  3. A-Level Law: Criminal Causation Scenario + Model + Plan

    criminal law essay on causation

  4. Essay About Causation in Criminal Law

    criminal law essay on causation

  5. Criminal Law

    criminal law essay on causation

  6. Article on Causation

    criminal law essay on causation

COMMENTS

  1. Discuss Causation in Criminal Law

    Discuss Causation in Criminal Law. Generally, causation can be said to be a difficult area of law. [ 2] Causation could be proved either through factual or legal causation. According to the Court of Appeal in Pagett [ 3] and Cheshire [ 4] the issue of factual causation is mainly one for the jury once it has been determined by the courts that ...

  2. Law of Causation Essay

    Law of Causation Essay. Critically explain and discuss the law of causation, covering all relevant issues, including the general principles of causation and the situations in which the chain of causation is broken. Result crimes are described as criminal offences, that require a prohibited result as an essential element and the required ...

  3. 4.3 Causation and Harm

    Causation in Fact. Every causation analysis is twofold. First, the defendant must be the factual or but for cause of the victim's harm. The but for term comes from this phrase: "but for the defendant's act, the harm would not have occurred" (Del. Code Ann. tit. II, 2011). As the Model Penal Code states, " [c]onduct is the cause of a ...

  4. What is Meant by 'Causation' in Criminal Law?

    Share this: Facebook Twitter Reddit LinkedIn WhatsApp. "Causation" in Criminal Law is concerned with whether the defendant's conduct contributed sufficiently to the prohibited consequence to justify the criminal liability, which would be assessed from two aspects, namely "factual" and "legal" causation. Factual causation requires ...

  5. Causation, Fault, and Fairness in the Criminal Law

    See AP Simester, "Causation in (Criminal) Law" (2017) 133 Law Q Rev 416 at 416-18. See generally Alan Norrie, "A Critique of Criminal Causation" (1991) 54 Mod L ... See HLA Hart, Punishment and Responsibility: Essays in the Philosophy of Law, 2nd ed (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2008) at 152-53; Colvin, supra note 36 at 263.

  6. Causation

    Abstract. This chapter examines the role of causation in criminal law and especially as a central ingredient of criminal responsibility. It first discusses whether results should matter in the determination of legal and moral responsibility before considering causation within the contexts of criminal law and tort law.

  7. Causation

    The chapter provides an account of causation in the criminal law that points toward some natural-world property that it (in part) rests upon, and which shows how that property is capable of bearing the moral freight that causation doctrines must carry. The account seeks to reconcile the tension between pre- and post-legal notions of causation ...

  8. PDF CAUSATION IN CRIMINAL LAW By DANIEL JAMES BANSAL

    resulting harm in criminal law. This thesis explores the resulting jurisprudence and argues that the absence of an explicit culpability-based criterion within the causation doctrines accounts for the courts' difficulties. The aim of this thesis, therefore, is to present a normative yet practical account of how the criminal law should ...

  9. Causation in the Criminal Law

    Abstract. This chapter notes that the law has a bafflingly large number of legal tests for causation. There is no universally accepted theory in the general part of the law of crimes. There are thousands of separate usages of "cause" in the thousands of liability rules of criminal law; and there are nine variations of cause-in-fact tests ...

  10. Causation in Criminal Liability and Reforms Essay

    Firstly, the causation in criminal liability implies the understanding of whether the defendant could be considered as a cause of the damage (Brody and Acker 115). In turn, it is divided into factual and legal causation (Bacigal and Tate 32). The core goal of this essay is to evaluate different types of causation and introduce reforms for ...

  11. (PDF) Causation in (Criminal) Law

    Causation in (Criminal) Law. Causal language is pervasive in the law, especially in those areas, such as contract law, tort law and criminal law, that deal with legal responsibility for the adverse consequences of voluntary and involuntary human interactions. Yet there are widely varying theories on the nature and role of causation in the law.

  12. Criminal Law: Causation

    Reasonable or foreseeable third-party actions will not break causation: R v Pagett (1983) 76 Cr App R 279.Completely unforeseeable acts, or fully informed, unreasonable and voluntary acts of third parties may break causation, however: R v Latif [1996] 2 Cr App r 92.Generally, the criminal law is far less willing than tort to find that the act of third parties (even negligent or deliberate acts ...

  13. PDF Causation in the Criminal Law It

    ItCausation in the Criminal LawIt's an interesting question why the actus reus of some offences are defined in terms of D's action (or breach of duty, where D is only 'guilty' of an omission) causing an outcome to occur (for example, murder, s.20 OAPA, s. 18 OAPA), and the actus reus of other offences are simply defined in terms of D ...

  14. Essay on causation Structure

    Give roadmap for your essay: Factual causation and legal causation. The issue regarding legal causation, third parties, medical negligence, victims own preexisting conditions etc. mention how the law regarding egg shell skull rule doesn't per se apply on escaping victims and suicide cases. lastly how does novus actus intravenous apply for ...

  15. A Review of Crime-Causation

    This essay briefly reviews the history of leading crime-causation theories and shows that research reveals prospects of some of them developing into lawlike principles for better guidance of criminal justice policies. To serve this essay's argument that causal theory is germane to public policy on crime, Section I reviews major historical

  16. The Nature of Causation

    Abstract. This chapter is concerned with the best way to understand causation in the criminal law. It is argued that there is a close parallel, with respect to central doctrines of causation, between causation in law and morality on the one hand and causation in science on the other. However, in law and morality we cannot separate the question ...

  17. Essay on causation

    causation essay result crimes are described as criminal offences, that require prohibited result as an essential element and the required consequence must. ... This is a concern of ́causation ́ in criminal law. Causation is recognised as a challenging issue within the criminal justice system. It has been a subject of discussion for scholars ...

  18. Criminal Law Essays

    Law of Causation Essay. Example essay. Last modified: 10th May 2021. Critically explain and discuss the law of causation, covering all relevant issues, including the general principles of causation and the situations in which the chain of causation is broken....

  19. Rethinking Causation in English Criminal Law

    in English criminal law, this leads Hart and Honoré to conclude that English criminal law is concerned with common-sense notions of causation. However, common-sense views of causation are decient because there are clear-cut situations where. fi. moral responsibility is irrelevant to causation. Take the vase example.

  20. Causation in (Criminal) Law

    Abstract. Analyses the elements of causation in criminal law, with reference to the real-world processes involved. Discusses direct causation arising from physical chain reactions of consecutive events, including the operating cause requirement, and highlights how the analysis differs from that used in R. v Hughes (Michael) (SC).

  21. Causation Is Only Important in Situation Where a Crime ...

    Causation would be virtually impossible to prove in the context of joint enterprise liability e.g. where A and B intends to commit burglary and B along the line commits murder. The modern law of causation would prevent any secondary liability from being established in many cases.

  22. Causation in criminal law (Essay, BCL, 1st year)

    The crux of this essay is to critically analyse each of the tests that form altogether the legal notion of causation as well as determining which test is the most accurate in order to establish causation. Factual Causation The factual causation involves first the necessity of the defendant's act to have caused the result or consequence : that ...